Placeholder Image

字幕表 動画を再生する

  • My name is Tamar Gendler.  I'm professor of philosophy and cognitive science and chair

  • of the philosophy department at Yale University.  

  • So philosophy comes from the Greek term meaning love of wisdom; philo, love; sophos, wisdom

  • and every culture from time immemorial has had a philosophical tradition.  There are

  • philosophical traditions in western culture that have their roots in ancient Greece

  • There are philosophical traditions in eastern culture, great Chinese and Indian philosophical

  • traditionsThere are philosophical traditions in AfricaThere are philosophical traditions

  • in native cultures throughout the worldWhat philosophy does in every society of which

  • it is a part is asks the question why, why are things that way they are and should they

  • be that wayThe western philosophical tradition to which

  • my comments today will be restricted can be divided into two main segmentsOn the one

  • hand it has a descriptive component, which asks about how things are and how we know

  • that and on the other hand it has a normative component, a component which asks about how

  • things ought to beSo into the first category fall questions like what is the fundamental

  • nature of reality, does God exist, do we have free willThose branches of philosophy are known as

  • metaphysics, fundamental questions about what there is, and epistemology, fundamental questions

  • about how we know things. On the other side of the divide are the questions that I've

  • called normative  questions, questions about values and that segment of philosophy has

  • three main partsOne of them, aesthetics is concerned with the question what is beautiful

  • and what makes it soThe second part of that division of philosophy, moral philosophy

  • asks the question what is morally right or good and the third part of that division of

  • philosophy, political philosophy asks the question how should societies be structured

  • in order to allow human flourishing and what makes societal structures legitimate           

  • Perhaps the most accessible and exciting part of philosophy for people who have never encountered

  • the discipline before is political philosophy, which asks questions that we as citizens of

  • a democracy need to ask ourselves in order to be responsible participants in our joint

  • governance, questions like what is the best way for society to be structured in order

  • to allow people to flourish, questions like what is the appropriate division of rights

  • and responsibilities in a society, questions like how should the legitimate concerns of

  • liberty on the one hand and equality on the other be balanced and for those of you who

  • are interested in studying a subject that has practical import it may be worth realizing

  • that political philosophy brought you the world as you know it todayPolitical philosophy

  • brought the world Greek democracy.  It brought us the Magna CartaIt brought us the French

  • Revolution and the American RevolutionIt brought us communismIt brought us the

  • Civil Rights MovementIt brought us feminism and libertarianismIt even brought us the

  • Tea Party.  It was, as a result of thinking about these sorts of questions that these

  • movements came into being.

  • So I want you to start by asking yourself how you would answer these questionsShould

  • the State guarantee universal healthcareShould there be an inheritance taxShould

  • there be a draft army and should you be allowed to sell your vote

  • The three people well meet in the lecture are Thomas Hobbes who wrote a great book called

  • Leviathan in 1651, John Rawls who wrote a book called Theory of Justice in 1971 and

  • Robert Nozick who wrote a book called Anarchy, State and Utopia in 1974. It has been said

  • that political philosophy asks two questions, who should get what and who says so and you

  • might think of the three authors that were going to discuss as answering those questions

  • in different waysThomas Hobbes is primarily concerned with

  • the second question who says so, what makes the State legitimate and John Rawls and Robert

  • Nozick are in a conversation directly with one another about the question who gets what.

  • So Thomas Hobbes lived at the end of the 1500s and beginning of the 1600s roughly at the

  • time of Shakespeare and if you read Hobbes work in the original youll notice that

  • the language in which he wrote was somewhat archaic, but the questions with which he is

  • concerned in his great book Leviathan aren’t questions that just apply to his time, theyre

  • questions that concern us today as well. He asks the question what would the world be

  • like if there wasn’t a state and would that situation be better or worse than the situation

  • where there is some form of governanceIn particular, Hobbes famously asks people

  • to imagine what life would be like in what he calls the state of nature,

  • a situation in which there is no external governing body and Hobbes points out that

  • in the state of nature people are all roughly equal in the following relevant wayAll

  • of us, no matter how physically strong or intellectually clever are at risk of having

  • the work that we do disrupted by others, at risk of having the property that weve acquired

  • taken by others, at risk of having the things that we see as important to our lives destroyed

  • by others because all of us sleep and all of us go away from things that are important

  • to usAs a result says Hobbes, in the state of nature

  • people need to expand a tremendous amount of energy protecting their goodsthere

  • is no opportunity in the state of nature to do the sorts of things which human beings

  • think makes life valuable, things like develop relationships to individuals far from us,

  • things like Hobbes mentions creating the skills of navigation, writing poetry, making music

  • or any of the things that you find valuable in your lifeAll of those things Hobbes

  • point out are possible only because you have a kind of security and safety.

By contrast,

  • life in the state of nature says Hobbes, is solitary, poor, nasty, broodish and short

  • The question is how can we get out of the state of natureHow can we get out of this

  • situation of perpetual fear, for as Hobbes point out active war isn’t what disrupts

  • human activityThe fear of war is sufficient to disrupt human activityThink of the

  • ways in which after 9/11 your anxiety about your security was raised so that at every

  • moment you were attentive to things around you, hyper vigilant to what risks you might

  • faceSo Hobbesidea in arguing for the legitimacy of government is to begin by asking

  • what would it be like if there were no government and to point out that that’s a state which

  • all of us find undesirable. There are says Hobbes, three things which

  • motivate people to try to leave the state of natureThey are, to quote directly,

  • fear of death, desire of such things as are necessary for commodious living and the

  • hope by their industry to obtain them”.  

  • So the puzzle the Hobbes raises is how can we get out of the state of nature and in subsequent

  • years game theorists who work at the intersection of what you might think of as philosophy and

  • economics have developed a way of representing the problem which Hobbes thinks we face in

  • the state of nature.

  • Life in the state of nature, according to Hobbes, embodies what is sometimes called

  • a prisoner’s dilemmaThe prisoner’s dilemma gets its name from a famous example

  • .  A small town police officer has captured two criminals and he wants to entice them

  • to confess, so what he does is he creates a structure of prison sentences where it’s

  • advantageous for each of the prisoners to confess regardless of what the other one does.

  • We can illustrate a prisoner’s dilemma by thinking about the situation of the United

  • States and the Soviet Union during the Cold WarBoth sides would have preferred de-escalation

  • in terms of armamentBoth sides would have been happy to use the money that they were

  • building missiles with to build schools and highways and hospitals, but both sides also

  • realized that if they engaged in unilateral disarmament they would be at riskLet’s

  • look at the structure that governed the choice that those two countries faced.

  • The United States couldn’t choose whether the Soviet Union disarmed or notIt could

  • only choose whether it disarmedThe Soviet Union couldn’t choose whether the United

  • States disarmed or notIt could only choose whether it disarmedFor both countries

  • their first choice was that the other country disarmed while they kept their weapons

  • Because of that what was rational for both countries to do was to keep their arms

  • What that meant is that the rational choice for both parties was to keep their arms rather than ending up in their

  • second choice situation, the situation where I have money to spend on my schools and hospitals

  • and Russia has money to spend on its schools and hospitals both countries in order to be

  • rational needed to spend resources on armamentThis structure occurs over and over again

  • in human transactions. So unless there is some sort of enforcement mechanism in place

  • we will end up like the US and the Soviet Union during the arms race, with our third

  • choice situation.

So the general problem with which the prisoner’s dilemma confronts

  • us is that if we behave in rational ways we will always end up not cooperating and the

  • puzzle that Hobbesconfronts in his political philosophy is the question how is it possible

  • to bring human beings into their second choice situation, where they cooperate with one another

  • rather than competing. It turns out that in lots of small local interactions

  • human beings do manage to find a way out of this scenarioFamously, during the First

  • World War when soldiers were engaged in trench warfare the Germans and the Americans developed

  • a kind of truce whereby soldiers from one side could leave their trenches and get some

  • fresh air without getting shot and then soldiers from the other side would leave their trenches

  • and get some fresh air without getting shotThe idea was that as long as the other side

  • was behaving peacefully it was rational for you to behave peacefully as well

  • If you fail to cooperate or if it seems to me that you have failed to cooperate I will

  • retaliate by not cooperatingBecause of the possibility that informal modes of cooperation

  • can breakdown Hobbes insisted that in order to get out of the state of nature we need

  • not only informal arrangements with one another, but a body that regulates human interactions

  • Hobbes concludes that it’s in our rational self interest to submit our will to a sovereign

  • whom he calls the Leviathan and thereby to get ourselves out of the state of nature.

  • Let’s fast forward 300 years. A half century later philosopher John Locke writes another

  • book about social contract theory and 50 or so years after that the philosopher John Jacques

  • Rousseau writes a similar work, each of them refining Hobbesnotion of the social contract

  • Together these three pictures of what makes a state legitimate allow the thinkers who

  • lie at the heart of the American and French Revolutions to articulate a picture of human

  • rights that makes those revolutions legitimateFrom the French and American Revolutions which

  • give voice to the citizens we move through the 18th century to the emancipation of the

  • serfs in Russia and a general democratization of society, a recognition that individual’s

  • votes should not be dependent upon them being landholders, but should rather be open to

  • people of all social classesExtending this idea Karl Marx writes the Communist

  • Manifesto and an entire enormous nation, Russia in 1917 reshapes the fundamental structure

  • of its society in response to a work of political philosophyAt the same time the tradition

  • which gave rise to the revolutions in the 18th century, one that says all human beings

  • have the right to have their voices heard, gives rise on the one hand to the women’s

  • voting movement in England and America and then to the Civil Rights movement on United

  • Statessoil expanding and expanding out of Hobbesfundamental idea that a government

  • to be legitimate, must be in response to the needs of its peopleWe get during this

  • 300 year period an incredible opening up of political rights of a sort unknown in the

  • history of civilization. Political philosopher John Rawls was born

  • in the early 20th century in the American southHe was of a generation where he and

  • all his friends went off to serve in the Second World War and returned from that war concerned

  • with how it’s possible to create a stable and just societyRawls spent most of his

  • academic career thinking about that question as a professor of philosophy at Harvard University

  • and when he was in his early 50s in the middle of the 1960s and early 1970s as the Vietnam

  • War was raging, as social protests were going on around him, as American society was reshaping

  • itself in ways that voice was given to the needs of the disenfranchised, Rawls tried

  • to articulate in the great social contract tradition a picture of what a just society

  • looks like and how a just society should be structured.

  • It’s in this time that John Rawls sets out to write his work, The Theory of JusticeIt’s

  • worth listening to the extraordinary opening words of RawlsbookHe says, “Justice

  • is the first virtue of social institutions as truth is of systems of thought.”  

  • Rawlsfundamental assumption in articulating what a just society looks like is that each

  • person possesses a certain inviolability which cannot be overridden even if doing so would

  • be of greater benefit to the society as a wholeIn so doing he challenges what had

  • become a dominant picture of what justice and morality demandThat picture can be

  • traced to the 19th century works of the British philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart

  • Mill and is known and utilitarianismIt’s an incredibly appealing view

  • What the view says is that an act is morally right if it produces the greatest good for

  • the greatest number of peopleIf I face a choice between saving one person and saving

  • five where I can save only one group or the other, utilitarianism gives what many people

  • find to be the intuitive answer that I should save the five, thereby bringing about more

  • happiness rather than the oneThe problem with utilitarianism that Rawls

  • is concerned with is that it seems that in farfetched and typical circumstances utilitarianism

  • could demand that we violate the rights of the one to help the many.  A famous counter

  • example to utilitarianism is that a healthy man walks into a hospital where there are

  • five dying individuals, one in need of a heart, one in need of a kidney, one in need of a

  • liver and two others each in need of parts that he hasThe utilitarian rubric would

  • seem to suggest that if those five can be saved by harming him that that’s what morality

  • demands. This picture that each of us has inviolable rights and that those rights can’t

  • be overridden by the needs of others is part of what is new and exciting in Rawlsdiscussion.

  • Taking as his premise the idea that justice is the first virtue of social institutions

  • that is that no unjust society is a legitimate one Rawls asks the following questionHow

  • should the benefits and burdens of living together in a community be distributed so

  • as to best realize what justice requiresIn particular, he asks what should the fundamental

  • institutional structures look like to allow a society to be a just society

  • Rawls sees himself as the inheritor of the social contract tradition of which Hobbes

  • was the initial voice in the western traditionLike Hobbes, Rawls asks what would people

  • choose to have their society look like if they were building it from the ground up.

  •  Rawls says a just society is one that rational, free and equal people would choose to contract

  • into, but we enter our interactions with one another will all sorts of inequalities in

  • placeSome of us are wealthySome of us are poorSome of us are endowed with

  • certain kinds of intellectual or physical skills that others lackIf we try to build

  • our society taking into consideration those facts about ourselves we aren’t doing it

  • from a position of equality, so Rawlsinsight is that sometimes the fairest way to make

  • a decision is to put yourself in a position where you have less information.

  • Think about what the fairest way to divide a cake isThe fairest way to divide a cake

  • is to ask you to divide it not knowing which piece youre going to getIf you divide

  • the cake unaware of which part will be yours you will be inclined to divide it in a fair

  • way. This is the veil of ignorance Let’s go behind the veil of ignorance and

  • ask a question that Rawls asks, namely, which of the two principles that he has derived

  • ought to take priority over the otherDo we care more about fundamental rights or do

  • we care about the distribution of incomeSo suppose youre faced with a choice of

  • three societies in which you can live not knowing what role you will play in the society

  • In society number one the average income is $100,000, but only 85% of the people have

  • fundamental rights, only 85% of the people have the right to vote, liberty of conscience,

  • the right to a fair trialIn the second society the average salaryin the second

  • society the average salary is $70,000 and only 85% of people have fundamental rights

  • In the third society the average salary is $70,000, but 100% of people have the right

  • to vote, freedom of expression, the right to a fair trialWhich society would you

  • choose to live in, average income of %100,000, 85% free, average income of $70,000, 85 % free

  • or average income $70,000, 100% freeWhen confronted with this choice set anybody who

  • is paying attention rejects the second optionIt has all of the disadvantages of the first

  • and all of the disadvantages of the third, but it’s also true that when confronted

  • with this choice almost everybody rejects the first option as wellIf you don’t

  • know whether youre going to be one of the ones with freedom then even though youre

  • guaranteed to have a higher income in the first society than the third more than 95%

  • of people choose to live in the third society. This idea that when you don’t know where

  • youre going to end up you have an inclination to be risk adverse is what lies behind Rawls

  • conclusions about what would be chosen from behind the veil of ignorance.

  • People want to make sure that the bottom is safe before they worry about what the top

  • looks like, so Rawls suggests that to the extent there are inequalities in a society

  • they should satisfy two conditions. So the first condition is that the benefits

  • of those inequalities be accessible to all and the second and perhaps most controversial

  • part of Rawlstheory is that to the extent that there are inequalities in a society they

  • should be distributed in such a way that they are to the benefit of the least well off,

  • so if it turns out that having a lower tax rate in the highest bracket produces wealth

  • and income in a way that leads those in the poorest quintile to benefit Rawls says that’s

  • okay, but if it turns out that that’s advantageous only to those in the highest segment of society

  • that inequality, says Rawls wouldn’t be countenanced from behind the veil of ignorance

  • It isn’t a way that people would choose for a society to be structured if their fundamental

  • concern was with justice. In 2005 two psychologists inspired by the

  • work of John Rawls decided to survey several thousand randomly selected Americans about

  • what they thought the distribution of income would look like in a society of which they

  • would want to be a part and they presented those citizens with two different pie graphs.

  • In the one, which you can see on the top the vast majority of wealth was held by the top

  • quintile of society and a small amount by the second quintile with virtually none held

  • by the remainder of the society. In the other the distribution was more equalRoughly

  • a third of the wealth was held by the top quintile and the remainder was distributed

  • among the remaining fourGiven the choice between those two social structures 92% of

  • Americans chose the bottomAs a matter of fact the top graph, which only 8% of subjects

  • chose represents the actual distribution of wealth in contemporary America, whereas the

  • bottom graph represents the actual distribution of wealth in contemporary Sweden.                      

  • The distribution of wealth where no more than 60% of the wealth is held by the top fifth

  • and where at least some of the wealth is held by the bottom two-fifths seems to be an ideal

  • for all Americans, not just for those who would benefit thereby.

  • Rich people and poor people give the same answer from behind the veil of ignorance

  • Men and women give the same answer from behind the veil of ignoranceReligious and nonreligious

  • people give the same answer from behind the veil of ignorance and perhaps most strikingly

  • democrats and republicans give roughly the same answer from behind the veil of ignorance.

  • As a matter of fact, 85% of the nation’s wealth is held by the top quintile, roughly

  • 10% by the second, roughly 5% by the middle and virtually none of the nation’s wealth

  • by 40% of the country. Does that mean our society is fundamentally

  • unjustJohn Rawls would give the answer yesBy contrast Robert Nozick would give

  • the answer no. because the structure of society in which we find ourselves is one that has

  • arisen as the result of voluntary interactions, of human beings engaged in legitimate transactions

  • whatever distribution results, says Nozick, is a just one

  • While John Rawls was writing Theory of Justice as a distinguished philosopher in his mid

  • 50s having fought in the Second World War and then taught philosophy for many decades

  • thereafterDown the hall from him was a precocious young man in his late 20s who had

  • recently started teaching at HarvardThat young man by the name of Robert Nozick took

  • upon himself the task of writing a rebuttal to RawlsTheory of Justice. And three years

  • after Theory of Justice was published Nozick published his retort, Anarchy, State and Utopia.

  • Nozick was concerned that Rawls had placed the wrong fundamental notion at the center

  • of his theory. Nozick writes:  “Individuals have rights

  • and there are things that no person or group may do to them without violating those rights

  • The minimal state limited to narrow functions of protection against force, theft and fraud,

  • enforcement of contracts and so on is the most extensive state that can be justified.” 

  • Like Rawls, Nozick is challenging the utilitarian pictureLike Rawls, Nozick thinks the goods

  • of one person can’t be traded off the goods of the community, but unlike Rawls Nozick

  • places at the center of his political philosophy not the notion of equality or justice, but

  • rather the notion of liberty. Let’s look at what a society governed by

  • Nozick’s principles might look likeNozick famously articulates a view of the conditions

  • under which property is legitimately held and his view is thisIt’s legitimate

  • for you to own something if you acquired it in a legitimate way when it was un-owned or

  • if you acquired it in a legitimate way from somebody else who already owned itIf I

  • got the property from you as the result of your having given it to me then no one can

  • legitimately take that property away from meThis may sound relatively uncontroversial,

  • but let’s look and see what it impliesSuppose each of us starts out with the same

  • amount of moneySay each of us has $100 and there are thousands and thousands of us

  • all of whom are fans of the great 1970s basketball star Wilt Chamberlain, so suppose you give

  • 25 cents of your money to Wilt Chamberlain and I give 25 cents of my money to Wilt Chamberlain

  • and our friend gives 25 cents of his money to Wilt Chamberlain and so on thousands and

  • thousands of times until Wilt Chamberlain comes to have not the $100 with which each

  • of us started out, but thousands and thousands and thousands of dollarsOn Nozick’s

  • picture any decision to take away any of the money which Wilt Chamberlain got through this

  • voluntary and legitimate transaction is a violation of rights. Then no distribution

  • of income, including one in which 1% of the people own 99% of the wealth could ever be

  • illegitimate because what matters is how it actually came into beingIf all that 99%

  • of the wealth came to those individuals as the result of legal transactions then nothing

  • can be done without violating rights to redistribute it.

  • There is no easy answer to this questionThere is a strong intuitive pull to the view

  • that Nozick advocatesit is in some sense theft to take from Wilt Chamberlain what each

  • of us has voluntarily given to himOn the other hand without such theft, more commonly

  • known by the term taxation, we will find ourselves perhaps in the sort of situation that neither

  • Rawls nor Nozick wants to be in. If all of us give our quarters to Wilt Chamberlain

  • and his companions. Instead of having a society of which were

  • all equally a part Wilt and his wealthy friends are able to buy access to the media, are able

  • to buy advertising time for candidates that they support, are able to send their children

  • to schools where they gain power and advantage and access to resources with the result that

  • the fundamental rights which Nozick as well as Rawls was concerned with preserving become

  • difficult for people to exercise.   The Wilt Chamberlain example illustrates a

  • general phenomenon which we face in a society, one which was foreshadowed in our discussion

  • of prisoner’s dilemmaIndividual decisions that are acceptable may be problematic if

  • large numbers of people make those decisionsThe problem that this gives rise to is sometimes

  • called the Tragedy of the Commons, so suppose there is a green area where I let

  • my cow graze and you let your cow graze and our neighbor lets his cow grazeSo far

  • no problem, for each of our cows there is enough to eat, but suppose that each of us

  • instead of having one cow has 50.  If you alone had 50 cows there would be no problem

  • If I alone had 50 cows there would be no problem, but if hundreds of us have 50 cows the entire

  • green space will disappear and all of our cows will dieThis structure manifests

  • itself in situation after situationOver fishing results from each of us taking what

  • would be a fine amount of fish if were the only ones doing it, but an amount that becomes

  • problematic if others are doing likewiseEach of us polluting a small amount causes

  • no problemAll of us polluting together can lead to drastic consequences.

  • Let’s return to our four opening questions and ask what Rawls and Nozick would say about

  • them. —with respect to the question of whether societies should guarantee universal healthcare

  • Rawls would say yes and Nozick would say noOn Rawlspicture health is a precondition

  • for participation in a civic society and from behind the veil of ignorance clearly everyone

  • would choose a society in which they had the guarantee of safety on Rawlspicture

  • By contrast, on Nozick’s this provision would be possible only as the result of illegitimate

  • interference in people’s livesWith respect to the question of whether an

  • inheritance tax is legitimate Rawls would say yes, Nozick noRawls says each of us

  • has the right to be born into a roughly equal community and those who inherit large amounts

  • at the moment of birth are disadvantaged in ways which presumably is not to the benefit

  • of the least well off.  Nozick by contrast wonders where Rawls gets the idea that it’s

  • anybody’s business to tell me whether I can give my money to my children.

  • With respect to the third question should the army be constituted by draft or by volunteers

  • Rawls would, at least in conditions of wartime, advocate a draft army.—just as the benefits

  • and rights of a society that are fundamental need to be distributed equally across all

  • so to on a Rawlspicture must the burdensThe only fair way to distribute those sorts

  • of responsibilities is as the result of a random processNozick by contrast would

  • be happy with a volunteer armyIndividuals have the right to contract into risk and the

  • fact that most of the individuals who contract into risky situations are those for whom there

  • are not so many options isn’t something that would bother Nozick, though of course

  • under both circumstances there are many who would choose to serve their societysimply

  • out of a desire to protect it. Finally, with respect to the question should

  • it be legitimate to sell your vote Rawls gives the answer noThat is a right that he considers

  • unalienable, unalienable because from behind a veil of ignorance we saw that no one would

  • choose to live in a society where such rights weren’t distributed equallyNozick by

  • contrast thinks that this, like everything else should be something which is your discretion

  • to choose and if you decide that one of the best ways for you to finance something that

  • you care about is by selling your vote to another person what business is it of anybody

  • else to tell you that you can’t.  You, I imagine, have your own answers to those

  • four questionsPerhaps they line up completely with one or the other of the authors that

  • weve discussed, but what you now have in addition to your answers to those questions

  • are some tools for thinking about why you give those answers.

  • When I graduated from college I spent a couple of years doing education policy work and then

  • decided to go back to graduate school to study philosophyIn 1990 I was lucky enough to

  • enroll as a graduate student at Harvard University where two of my teachers were the political

  • philosopher John Rawls and a man who ended up being my dissertation director Robert Nozick

  • It’s from the two of them that I learned what I know about political philosophy.

  • What political philosophy and philosophy in general encourages you to do is to step outside

  • the specificity of your own situationHobbes and Rawls and Nozick all recognized that each

  • of us wants more rather than less of a share of the goods of our society, but what they

  • ask you to do is to think about how the fact that you want more rather than less suggests

  • that everyone else probably does too. Philosophy has always been connected to the

  • works that are going on in other fields at its timeIn ancient Greece the philosopher

  • Aristotle was not only doing work in metaphysics and epistemologyHe was collecting constitutions

  • from various other Greek city states to provide the first catalog of political systems

  • He was doing biological experiments and thinking about the nature of physicsIn the early

  • modern period philosophers like Rene Descartes or Thomas Hobbes were major contributors not

  • just to the philosophical work of their time, but also to the scientific workDescartes

  • invented coordinate geometry, which we still know by the name Cartesian geometry and Hobbes

  • did work not just in the domain of political philosophy, but also work in the sciences

  • This has been true throughout philosophy’s history that it’s great thinkers think not

  • only about questions central to the discipline, but also about how those questions relate

  • to the fields around them, so philosophers of mind right now contribute to debates about

  • the nature of consciousness thinking both about what it is for people to be conscious

  • and making use of the resources of a 500 year-old tradition of thinking about the relation between

  • mind and body. People who major in philosophy have gone

  • on to do a huge range of things. They go to law schoolThey go to business school

  • They go to medical schoolSome of them  go onto be philosophers in a professional

  • sense, but what philosophers typically go onto do is to be thoughtful, reflective participants

  • in whatever they end up doing whether that be working in real estate or working as a

  • nurse or being a fulltime parent or being mayor of their town

  • The most profound questions of the world are the ones which philosophy gives you permission

  • to ask and to learn how to answer and it’s for that reason that the study of philosophy

  • can be an enormously illuminating and valuable part of anyone’s lifeThank youThank

  • youThank you.

My name is Tamar Gendler.  I'm professor of philosophy and cognitive science and chair

字幕と単語

ワンタップで英和辞典検索 単語をクリックすると、意味が表示されます

B1 中級

Tamar Gendler: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Politics and Economics !

  • 129 12
    fisher に公開 2013 年 03 月 24 日
動画の中の単語