Placeholder Image

字幕表 動画を再生する

  • Now we turn

  • Now we turn to the hardest philosopher we're going to read in this course.

  • Today we turn to Immanuel Kant

  • who offers a different account

  • of why we have a categorical duty

  • to respect the dignity of persons

  • and not to use people as means merely

  • even for good ends.

  • Kant excelled at the University of Konigsberg

  • at the age of 16.

  • At age of 31, he got his first job as an unsalaried lecturer

  • paid on commission based on the number of students

  • who showed up at his lectures.

  • This is a sensible system that Harvard would do well to consider.

  • Luckily for Kant, he was a popular lecturer

  • and also an industrious one

  • and so he eked out a meager living.

  • It wasn't until he was 57 that he published his first major work.

  • But, it was worth the wait,

  • the book was theCritique of Pure Reason

  • perhaps the most important work in all of modern philosophy.

  • And a few years later, Kant wrote the groundwork forMetaphysics of Morals

  • which we read in this course.

  • I want to acknowledge even before we start

  • that Kant is a difficult thinker

  • but it's important to try to figure what he's saying

  • because what this book is about

  • is what the supreme principle of morality is,

  • number one,

  • and it also gives us an account

  • one of the most powerful accounts we have

  • of what freedom really is.

  • So, let me start today,

  • Kant rejects utilitarianism.

  • He thinks that

  • the individual person,

  • all human beings,

  • have a certain dignity that commands our respect.

  • The reason the individual is sacred or the bearer of rights,

  • according to Kant,

  • doesn't stem from the idea that we own ourselves

  • but instead from the idea that we are all rational beings.

  • We're all rational beings, which simply means

  • that we are beings who are capable of reason.

  • We are also autonomous beings,

  • which is to say that we are beings capable of acting and choosing freely.

  • Now, this capacity for reason and freedom

  • isn't the only capacity we have.

  • We also have the capacity for pain and pleasure,

  • for suffering and satisfaction.

  • Kant admits the utilitarians were half right.

  • Of course, we seek to avoid pain

  • and we like pleasure,

  • Kant doesn't deny this.

  • What he does deny

  • is Bentham's claim

  • that pain and pleasure are our sovereign masters.

  • He thinks that's wrong.

  • Kant thinks that it's our rational capacity

  • that makes us distinctive,

  • that makes us special,

  • that sets us apart from and above mere animal existence.

  • It makes us something more than just physical creatures with appetites.

  • We often think of freedom as simply consisting in doing what we want

  • or in the absence of obstacles to getting what we want,

  • that's one way of thinking about freedom.

  • But this isn't Kant's idea of freedom.

  • Kant has a more stringent demanding notion

  • of what it means to be free.

  • And though it's stringent and demanding,

  • if you think it through, it's actually pretty persuasive.

  • Kant reasons as follows:

  • when we, like animals,

  • seek after pleasure or the satisfaction of our desires

  • or the avoidance of pain,

  • when we do that we aren't really acting freely.

  • Why not?

  • We're really acting as the slaves of those appetites and impulses.

  • I didn't choose this particular hunger or that particular appetite

  • and so when I act to satisfy it,

  • I'm just acting according to natural necessity.

  • And for Kant, freedom is the opposite of necessity.

  • There was an advertising slogan for the soft drink Sprite a few years ago.

  • The slogan was, “Obey your thirst.”

  • There's a Kantain insight buried in that Sprite advertising slogan

  • that in a way is Kant's point.

  • When you go for Sprite or Pepsi, you're really

  • you might think that you're choosing freely,

  • Sprite versus Pepsi,

  • but you're actually obeying something,

  • a thirst or maybe a desire manufactured or massaged by advertising,

  • you're obeying a prompting that you yourself haven't chosen or created.

  • And here it is worth noticing Kant's specially demanding idea of freedom.

  • What way of actinghow can my will be determined

  • if not by the promptings of nature

  • or my hunger or my appetite or my desires?

  • Kant's answer?

  • To act freely is to act autonomously,

  • and to act autonomously is to act according to a law

  • that I give myself

  • not according to the physical laws of nature

  • or the laws of cause and effect

  • which include my desire to eat or to drink

  • or to choose this

  • food in a restaurant over that.

  • Now, what is the opposite

  • of autonomy for Kant?

  • He invents a special term

  • to describe the opposite of autonomy.

  • Heteronomy is the opposite of autonomy.

  • When I act heteronomously, I'm acting according to an inclination,

  • or a desire, that I haven't chosen for myself.

  • So, freedom as autonomy is an especially stringent idea that Kant insists on.

  • Now, why is autonomy the opposite of acting heteronomously

  • or according to the dictates of nature?

  • Kant's point is that nature is governed by laws,

  • laws of cause and effect for example.

  • Suppose you drop a billiard ball,

  • it falls to the ground;

  • we wouldn't say the billiard ball is acting freely.

  • Why not?

  • It's acting according to the law of nature,

  • according to the laws of cause of effect,

  • the law of gravity.

  • And just as he has an unusually demanding and stringent

  • conception of freedom,

  • freedom as autonomy,

  • he also has a demanding conception of morality.

  • To act freely is not to choose the best means to a given end;

  • it's to choose the end itself for its own sake.

  • And that's something that human beings can do

  • and that billiard balls can't.

  • In so far as we act on inclination or pursue pleasure,

  • we act as means to the realization of ends given outside us.

  • We are instruments rather than authors of the purposes we pursue,

  • that's the heteronymous determination of the will.

  • On the other hand, in so far as we act autonomously,

  • according to a law we give ourselves,

  • we do something for its own sake as an end in itself.

  • When we act autonomously, we seize to be instruments

  • to purposes given outside us,

  • we become, or we can come to think of ourselves

  • as ends in ourselves.

  • This capacity to act freely, Kant tells us,

  • is what gives human life its special dignity.

  • Respecting human dignity means regarding persons

  • not just as means but also as ends in themselves.

  • And this is why it's wrong to use people

  • for the sake of other peoples' well-being or happiness.

  • This is the real reason, Kant says,

  • that utilitarianism goes wrong.

  • This is the reason it's important to respect the dignity of persons

  • and to uphold their rights.

  • So, even if there are cases, remember John Stewart Mill said,

  • Well, in the long run, if we uphold justice

  • and respect the dignity of persons,

  • we will maximize human happiness.”

  • What would Kant's answer be to that?

  • What would his answer be?

  • Even if that were true,

  • even if the calculus worked out that way,

  • even if you shouldn't throw the Christian's to the lions

  • because in the long run fear will spread,

  • the overall utility will decline.

  • The utilitarian would be upholding justice and right

  • and respect for persons for the wrong reason,

  • for a purely a contingent reason,

  • for an instrumental reason.

  • It would still be using people,

  • even where the calculus works out for the best in the long run,

  • it would still be using people as means

  • rather than respecting them as ends in themselves.

  • So, that's Kant's idea of freedom as autonomy

  • and you can begin to see how it's connected to his idea of morality.

  • But we still have to answer one more question,

  • what gives an act its moral worth in the first place?

  • If it can't be directed,

  • that utility or satisfying wants and desires,

  • what gives an action its moral worth?

  • This leads us from Kant's demanding idea of freedom

  • to his demanding idea of morality.

  • What does Kant say?

  • What makes an action morally worthy

  • consists not in the consequences or in the results that flow from it,

  • what makes an action morally worthy has to do with the motive,

  • with the quality of the will,

  • with the intention for which the act is done.

  • What matters is the motive

  • and the motive must be of a certain kind.

  • So, the moral worth of an action

  • depends on the motive for which it's done

  • and the important thing is that the person

  • do the right thing for the right reason.

  • "A good will isn't good because of what it affects or accomplishes,"

  • Kant writes, "it's good in itself.

  • Even if by its utmost effort, the goodwill accomplishes nothing,

  • it would still shine like a jewel for its own sake

  • as something which has its full value in itself."

  • And so, for any action to be morally good,

  • it's not enough that it should conform to the moral law,

  • it must also be done for the sake of the moral law.

  • The idea is that the motive confers the moral worth on an action

  • and the only kind of motive that can confer moral worth on an action

  • is the motive of duty.

  • Well, what's the opposite of doing something out of a sense of duty

  • because it's right?

  • Well for Kant,

  • the opposite would be all of those motives

  • having to do with our inclinations.

  • And inclinations refer to all of our desires,

  • all of our contingently given wants,

  • preferences, impulses, and the like.

  • Only actions done for the sake of the moral law,

  • for the sake of duty,

  • only these actions have moral worth.

  • Now, I want to see what you think about this idea

  • but first let's consider a few examples.

  • Kant begins with an example of a shopkeeper.

  • He wants to bring out the intuition

  • and make plausible the idea

  • that what confers moral worth on an action

  • is that it be done because it's right.

  • He says suppose there's a shopkeeper

  • and an inexperienced customer comes in.

  • The shopkeeper knows that he could give the customer the wrong change,

  • could shortchange the customer and get away with it;

  • at least that customer wouldn't know.

  • But the shopkeeper nonetheless says,

  • Well, if I shortchange this customer, word may get out,

  • my reputation would be damaged,

  • and I would loose business,

  • so I won't shortchange this customer.”

  • The shopkeeper does nothing wrong,

  • he gives the correct change,

  • but does his action have moral worth?

  • Kant says no, it doesn't have moral worth

  • because the shopkeeper only did the right thing for the wrong reason,

  • out of self-interest.

  • That's a pretty straightforward case.

  • Then he takes another case, the case of suicide.

  • He says we have a duty to preserve ourselves.

  • Now, for most people who love life,

  • we have multiple reasons for not taking our own lives.

  • So, the only way we can really tell,

  • the only way we can isolate the operative motive

  • for someone who doesn't take his or her life

  • is to thinkto imagine someone who's miserable

  • and who despite having an absolutely miserable life

  • nonetheless recognizes the duty to preserve one's self

  • and so does not commit suicide.

  • The force of the example is to bring out the motive that matters

  • and the motive that matters for morality

  • is doing the right thing for the sake of duty.

  • Let me just give you a couple of other examples.

  • The Better Business Bureau, what's their slogan?

  • The slogan of the Better Business Bureau:

  • "Honesty is the best policy.

  • It's also the most profitable."

  • This is the Better Business Bureau's full page ad in the New York Times,

  • "Honesty, it's as important as any other asset

  • because a business that deals in truth, openness, and fair value

  • cannot help but do well.

  • Come join us and profit from it."

  • What would Kant say about the moral worth

  • of the honest dealings of members of the Better Business Bureau?

  • What would he say?

  • That here's a perfect example that if this is the reason

  • that these companies deal honestly with their customers,

  • their action lacks moral worth, this is Kant's point.

  • A couple of years ago, at the University of Maryland,

  • there was a problem with cheating

  • and so they initiated an honor system

  • and they created a program with local merchants

  • that if you signed the honor pledge, a pledge not to cheat,

  • you would get discounts of 10% to 25% at local shops.

  • Well what would you think of someone motivated to uphold an honor code

  • with the hope of discounts?

  • It's the same as Kant's shopkeeper.

  • The point is, what matters is the quality of the will,

  • the character of the motive

  • and the relative motive to morality can only be the motive of duty,

  • not the motive of inclination.

  • And when I act out of duty,

  • when I resist as my motive for acting inclinations

  • or self-interest,

  • even sympathy and altruism,

  • only then am I acting freely,

  • only then am I acting autonomously,

  • only then is my will not determined or governed

  • by external considerations,

  • that's the link between Kant's idea of freedom and of morality.

  • Now, I want to pause here to see if all of this is clear

  • or if you have some questions or puzzles.

  • They can be questions of clarification

  • or they can be challenges.

  • If you want to challenge this idea that only the motive of duty

  • confers moral worth on the action.

  • What do you think?

  • Yes.

  • Yeah, I actually have two questions of clarification.

  • The first is, there seems to be an aspect of this

  • that makes it sort of self-defeating

  • in that once you're conscious of what morality is

  • you can sort of alter your motive to achieve that end of morality.

  • Give me an example of what you have in mind.

  • The shopkeeper example.

  • If he decides that he wants to give the person the money

  • to do the right thing

  • and he decides that it's his motive to do so

  • because he wants to be moral

  • then isn't that sort of defeating trying to

  • isn't that sort of defeating the purity of his action

  • if morality is determined by his motive?

  • His motive is then to act morally.

  • I see. So, you're imagining a case

  • not of the purely selfish calculating shopkeeper

  • but of one who says,

  • well, he may consider shortchanging the customer.

  • But then he says, "Not,

  • or my reputation might suffer if word gets out."

  • But instead he says,

  • "Actually, I would like to be the kind of honest person

  • who gives the right change to customers

  • simply because it's the right thing to do."

  • Or simply, "Because I want to be moral."

  • "Because I want to be moral, I want to be a good person,

  • and so I'm going to conform all of my actions

  • to what morality requires."

  • It's a subtle point, it's a good question.

  • Kant does acknowledge,

  • you're pressing Kant on an important point here,

  • Kant does say there has to be some incentive

  • to obey the moral law,

  • it can't be a self-interested incentive

  • that would defeat it by definition.

  • So, he speaks of a different kind of incentive from that inclination,

  • he speaks of reverence for the moral law.

  • So, if that shopkeeper says,

  • “I want to develop a reverence for the moral law

  • and so I'm going to do the right thing

  • then I think he's there,

  • he's there as far as Kant's concerned

  • because he's formed his motive,

  • his will is conforming to the moral law

  • once he sees the importance of it.

  • So, it would count, it would count.

  • All right, then, secondly, very quickly,

  • what stops morality from becoming completely objective in this point?

  • What stops morality from becoming subjective?

  • Yeah, like how canif morality is completely determined by your morals

  • then how can you apply this or how can it be enforced?

  • All right, that's also a great question.

  • -- What's your name? -- My name is Amady.

  • -- Amady? -- Yes.

  • All right, if acting morally

  • means acting according to a moral law out of duty

  • and if it's also to act freely in the sense of autonomously,

  • it must mean that I'm acting according to a law that I give myself,

  • that's what it means to act autonomously,

  • Amady is right about that,

  • but that does raise a really interesting question.

  • If acting autonomously means acting according to a law I give myself,

  • that's how I escape the chain of cause and effect and the laws of nature.

  • What's the guarantee that the law I give myself

  • when I'm acting out of duty

  • is the same as the law that Amady is giving himself

  • and that each of you gives yourselves?

  • Well, here's the question,

  • how many moral laws, from Kant's point of view,

  • are there in this room?

  • Are there a thousand or is there one?

  • He thinks there's one, which in a way does go back to this question:

  • all right, what is the moral law?

  • What does it tell us?

  • So, what guaranteesit sounds like to act autonomously

  • is to act according to one's conscience,

  • according to a law one gives oneself,

  • but what guarantees that we

  • if we all exercise our reason,

  • we will come up with one and the same moral law?

  • That's what Amady wants to know.

  • Here's Kant's answer:

  • the reason that leads us to the law we give ourselves

  • as autonomous beings is a reason,

  • it's a kind of practical reason that we share as human beings.

  • It's not idiosyncratic.

  • The reason we need to respect the dignity of persons

  • is that we're all rational beings,

  • we all have the capacity for reason

  • and it's the exercise of that capacity for reason

  • which exists undifferentiated in all of us

  • that makes us worthy of dignity, all of us,

  • and since it's the same capacity for reason,

  • unqualified by particular autobiographies and life circumstance,

  • it's the same universal capacity for reason

  • that delivers the moral law,

  • it turns out that to act autonomously

  • is to act according to a law we give ourselves exercising our reason,

  • but it's the reason we share with everyone as rational beings,

  • not the particular reasons we have given our upbringings,

  • our particular values, our particular interests.

  • It's pure practical reason, in Kant's terms,

  • which legislates a priori regardless of any particular contingent

  • or empirical ends.

  • Well, what moral law would that kind of reason deliver?

  • What is its content?

  • To answer that question, you have to read the groundwork

  • and we'll continue with that question next time.

  • For Kant, morally speaking, suicide is on a par with murder.

  • It's on a par with murder because what we violate

  • when we take a life,

  • when we take someone's life, ours or somebody else's,

  • we use that person, we use a rational being,

  • be use humanity as a means

  • and so we fail to respect humanity as an end.

  • Today we turn back to Kant.

  • Before we do, remember this is the week

  • by the end of which all of you will basically get Kant,

  • figure out what he's up to.

  • You're laughing.

  • No, it will happen.

  • Kant's groundwork is about two big questions.

  • First, what is the supreme principle of morality?

  • Second, how is freedom possible?

  • Two big questions.

  • Now, one way of making your way through this dense philosophical book

  • is to bear in mind a set of oppositions

  • or contrasts or dualisms

  • that are related.

  • Today I'd like to talk about them.

  • Today we're going to answer the question,

  • what, according to Kant, is the supreme principle of morality?

  • And in answering that question,

  • in working our way up to Kant's answer to that question

  • it will help to bear in mind

  • three contrasts, or dualisms,

  • that Kant sets out.

  • The first, you'll remember,

  • had to do with the motive according to which we act.

  • And according to Kant, only one kind of motive

  • is consistent with morality, the motive of duty,

  • doing the right thing for the right reason.

  • What other kind of motives are there?

  • Kant sums them up in the category of inclination.

  • Every time the motive for what we do is to satisfy a desire or a preference

  • that we may have, to pursue some interest,

  • we're acting out of inclination.

  • Now, let me pause to see if in thinking about the question

  • of the motive of duty, the goodwill,

  • see if any of you has a question about that much of Kant's claim.

  • Or is everybody happy with this distinction?

  • What do you think? Go ahead.

  • When you make that distinction between duty and inclination

  • is there ever any moral action ever?

  • I mean you could always, kind of, probably find some selfish motive, can't you?

  • Maybe, very often people do have self-interested motives when they act.

  • Kant wouldn't dispute that

  • but what Kant is saying is that in so far as we act morally,

  • that is in so far as our actions have moral worth,

  • what confers moral worth is precisely our capacity

  • to rise above self-interest and prudence and inclination

  • and to act out of duty.

  • Some years ago I read about a spelling bee

  • and there was a young man who was declared the winner

  • of the spelling bee,

  • a kid named Andrew, 13 years old.

  • The winning word, the word that he was able to spell,

  • wasecholalia.”

  • Does anyone know what echolalia is? What?

  • Some type of flower?

  • It's not some type of flower. No.

  • It means the tendency to repeat as in echo,

  • to repeat what you've heard.

  • Anyhow, he misspelled it actually but the judges misheard him,

  • they thought he had spelled it correctly

  • and awarded him the championship of the National Spelling Bee

  • and he went to the judges afterward and said,

  • Actually, I misspelled it, I don't deserve the prize.”

  • And he was regarded as a moral hero

  • and he was written up in the New York Times,

  • Misspeller is Spelling Bee Hero.”

  • There's Andrew with his proud mother

  • and when he was interviewed afterwards, listen to this,

  • when he was interviewed afterwards, he said,

  • The judges said I had a lot of integrity,”

  • but then he added that part of his motive was,

  • “I didn't want to feel like a slime.”

  • All right. What would Kant say?

  • Go ahead.

  • I guess it would depend on whether or not

  • that was a marginal reason or the predominant reason

  • and whether or notand why he decided to confess

  • that he didn't actually spell the word correctly.

  • Good. And what's your name?

  • Bosco.

  • That's very interesting.

  • Is there anyone else who has a view about this?

  • Does this show that Kant's principle is too stringent, too demanding?

  • What would Kant say about this?

  • Yes.

  • I think that Kant actually says that it is the pure motivation

  • that comes out of duty which gives the action moral worth.

  • So, it's like, for example in this case,

  • he might have more than one motive,

  • he might have the motive of not feeling like a slime

  • and he might have the motive of doing the right thing itself out of duty

  • and so, while there's more than one motivation going on there

  • doesn't mean that the action is devoid of moral worth

  • just because he has one other motive

  • because the motive which involves duty is what gives it the moral worth.

  • Good. And what's your name:

  • Judith.

  • Well Judith, I think that your account actually is true to Kant.

  • It's fine to have sentiments and feelings

  • that support doing the right thing provided they don't provide

  • the reason for acting.

  • So, I think Judith actually has mounted a pretty good defense of Kant

  • on this question of the motive of duty.

  • Thank you.

  • Now, let's go back to the three contrasts.

  • It's clear at least what Kant means when he says

  • that for an action to have moral worth, it must be done for the sake of duty,

  • not out of inclination.

  • But as we began to see last time,

  • there's a connection between Kant's stringent notion of morality

  • and his specially demanding understanding of freedom.

  • And that leads us to the second contrast,

  • the link between morality and freedom

  • The second contrast describes two different ways

  • that my will can be determined;

  • autonomously and heteronomously.

  • According to Kant, I'm only free when my will is determined autonomously.

  • Which means what?

  • According to a law that I give myself.

  • We must be capable, if we're capable of freedom as autonomy,

  • we must be capable of acting according not to a law

  • that's given or imposed on us

  • but according to a law we give ourselves.

  • But where could such a law come from?

  • A law that we give ourselves.

  • Reason.

  • If reason determines my will

  • then the will becomes a power to choose independent of the dictates of nature

  • or inclination or circumstance.

  • So, connected with Kant's demanding notions of morality and freedom

  • is a specially demanding notion of reason.

  • Well, how can reason determine the will?

  • There are two ways and this leads to the third contrast.

  • Kant says there are two different commands of reason

  • and a command of reason Kant calls an imperative

  • an imperative is simply an ought.

  • One kind of imperative, perhaps the most familiar kind,

  • is a hypothetical imperative.

  • Hypothetical imperatives use instrumental reason.

  • If you want x then do y.

  • It's means-ends reasoning.

  • If you want a good business reputation then don't shortchange your customers,

  • word may get out.

  • That's a hypothetical imperative.

  • "If the action would be good solely as a means to something else,"

  • Kant writes, "the imperative is hypothetical.

  • If the action is represented as good in itself

  • and therefore is necessary for a will which of itself accords with reason,

  • then the imperative is categorical."

  • That's the difference between a categorical imperative

  • and a hypothetical one.

  • A categorical imperative commands categorically,

  • which just means without reference to or dependence on any further purpose

  • and so you see the connection

  • among these three parallel contrasts.

  • To be free, in the sense of autonomous,

  • requires that I act not out of a hypothetical imperative

  • but out of a categorical imperative.

  • And so you see by these three contrasts Kant reasons his way,

  • brings us up to his derivation of the categorical imperative.

  • Well, this leaves us one big question:

  • what is the categorical imperative?

  • What is the supreme principle of morality?

  • What does it command of us?

  • Kant gives three versions, three formulations,

  • of the categorical imperative.

  • I want to mention two and then see what you think of them.

  • The first version, the first formula,

  • he calls the formula of the universal law;

  • "Act only on that maxim whereby you can at the same time will

  • that it should become a universal law."

  • And by maxim, what does Kant mean?

  • He means a rule that explains the reason for what you're doing,

  • a principle.

  • For example, promise keeping.

  • Suppose I need money, I need $100 desperately

  • and I know I can't pay it back anytime soon.

  • I come to you and make you a promise,

  • a false promise, one I know I can't keep,

  • Please give me $100 today, lend me the money,

  • I will repay you next week.”

  • Is that consistent with the categorical imperative,

  • that false promise?

  • Kant says no.

  • And the test, the way we can determine

  • that the false promise is at odds with the categorical imperative

  • is try to universalize it,

  • universalize the maxim upon which you're about to act.

  • If everybody made false promises when they needed money

  • then nobody would believe those promises,

  • there would be no such thing as a promise,

  • and so there would be a contradiction.

  • The maxim universalized would undermine itself.

  • That's the test.

  • That's how we can know that the false promise is wrong.

  • Well what about the formula of the universal law?

  • You find it persuasive?

  • What do you think? Go ahead.

  • I have a question about the difference between categoricalism

  • and a hypothesis that if you're going to act . . .

  • Between categorical and hypothetical.

  • Hypothetical, yeah.

  • Imperatives.

  • Right. If you're going to act with a categorical imperative

  • so that the maxim doesn't undermine itself,

  • it sounds like I am going to do x because I want y,

  • I'm going to not lie in dire need because I want the world to function

  • in such a way that promises are kept.

  • I don't want to liquidate the practice of promises.

  • Right, it sounds like justifying a means by an ends.

  • It seems like an instance of consequentialist reasoning,

  • you're saying. -- Right.

  • -- And what's your name? -- Tim.

  • Well Tim, John Stewart Mill agreed with you.

  • He made this criticism of Kant.

  • He said, “If I universalize the maxim and find that the whole practice

  • of promise keeping would be destroyed if universalized,

  • I must be appealing somehow to consequences

  • if that's the reason not to tell a false promise.”

  • So, John Stewart Mill agreed with that criticism against Kant

  • but John Stewart Mill was wrong.

  • You're in good company though. You're in good company, Tim.

  • Kant has often read, as Tim just read him,

  • as appealing to consequences.

  • The world would be worse off if everybody lied

  • because then no one could rely on anybody else's word

  • therefore you shouldn't lie.

  • That's not what Kant is saying exactly.

  • Although, it's easy to interpret him as saying that.

  • I think what he's saying is that this is the test,

  • this is the test of whether the maxim corresponds

  • with the categorical imperative.

  • It isn't exactly the reason, it's not the reason,

  • the reason you should universalize to test your maxim

  • is to see whether you are privileging your particular needs and desires

  • over everybody else's.

  • It's a way of pointing to this feature,

  • this demand of the categorical imperative

  • that the reasons for your action shouldn't depend

  • for their justification on your interests, your needs,

  • your special circumstances being more important than somebody else's.

  • That, I think, is the moral intuition lying behind the universalization test.

  • So, let me spell out the second,

  • Kant's second version of the categorical imperative,

  • perhaps in a way that's more intuitively accessible

  • than the formula of universal law.

  • It's the formula of humanity as an end.

  • Kant introduces the second version of the categorical imperative

  • with the following line of argument:

  • "We can't base the categorical imperative

  • on any particular interests, purposes, or ends

  • because then it would be only relative to the person whose ends they were.

  • But suppose, however, there was something whose existence has in itself

  • an absolute value . . . an end in itself . . .

  • then in it, and in it alone,

  • would there be the ground of a possible categorical imperative."

  • Well, what is there that we can think of

  • as having its end in itself?

  • Kant's answer is this, “I say that man,

  • and in general every rational being, exists as and end in himself,

  • not merely as a means for arbitrary use by this or that will.”

  • And here Kant distinguishes between persons on the one hand

  • and things on the other.

  • Rational beings are persons,

  • they don't just have a relative value for us

  • but if anything has they have an absolute value,

  • an intrinsic value, that is rational beings have dignity.

  • They're worthy of reverence or respect.

  • This line of reasoning leads Kant to the second formulation

  • of the categorical imperative which is this:

  • "Act in such a way that you always treat humanity,

  • whether in your own person or in the person of any other,

  • never simply as a means,

  • but always at the same time, as an end."

  • So, that's the formula of humanity as an end,

  • the idea that human beings as rational beings are ends in themselves,

  • not open to use merely as a means.

  • When I make a false promise to you,

  • I'm using you as a means to my ends,

  • to my desire for the $100,

  • and so I'm failing to respect you,

  • I'm failing to respect your dignity,

  • I'm manipulating you.

  • Now, consider the example of the duty against suicide.

  • Murder and suicide are at odds with the categorical imperative.

  • Why?

  • If I murder someone, I'm taking their life for some purpose,

  • either because I'm a hired killer

  • or I'm in the throes of some great anger passion,

  • I have some interest, some purpose,

  • that's particular for the sake which I'm using them as a means.

  • Murder violates the categorical imperative.

  • For Kant, morally speaking, suicide is on a par with murder.

  • It's on a par with murder because what we violate when we take a life,

  • when we take someone's life, ours or somebody else's,

  • we use that person, we use a rational being,

  • we use humanity as a means

  • and so we fail to respect humanity as an end.

  • And that capacity for reason, that humanity that commands respect,

  • that is the ground of dignity,

  • that humanity, that capacity for reason

  • resides undifferentiated in all of us

  • and so I violate that dignity in my own person, if I commit suicide,

  • and in murder if I take somebody else's life.

  • From a moral point of view they're the same

  • and the reason they're the same has to do with the universal character

  • and ground of the moral law.

  • The reason that we have to respect the dignity of other people

  • has not to do with anything in particular about them

  • and so respect, Kantian respect, unlike love in this way.

  • It's unlike sympathy.

  • It's unlike solidarity or fellow feeling or altruism

  • because love and those other particular virtues or reasons

  • for caring about other people have to do with who they are in particular.

  • But respect, for Kant,

  • respect is respect for humanity which is universal,

  • for a rational capacity which is universal,

  • and that's why violating it, in my own case,

  • is as objectionable as violating it in the case of any other.

  • Questions or objections?

  • Go ahead.

  • I guess I'm somewhat worried about Kant's statement

  • that you cannot use a person as a means

  • because every person is an end of themselves,

  • because it seems that everyday,

  • in order to get something accomplished for that day,

  • I must use myself as a means to some end

  • and I must use the people around me as a means to some end as well.

  • For instance, suppose that I want to do well in a class

  • and I have to write a paper.

  • I have to use myself as a means to write the paper.

  • Suppose I want to buy something, food,

  • I must go to the store and use the person working behind the counter

  • as a means for me to purchase my food.

  • Right. That's true, you do.

  • What's your name?

  • Patrick.

  • Patrick, you're not doing anything wrong.

  • You're not violating the categorical imperative

  • when you use other people as means,

  • that's not objectionable

  • provided when we deal with other people

  • for the sake of advancing our projects and purposes and interests,

  • which we all do,

  • provided we treat them in a way that is consistent

  • with respect for their dignity

  • and what it means to respect them

  • is given by the categorical imperative.

  • Are you persuaded?

  • Do you think that Kant has given a compelling account,

  • a persuasive account, of the supreme principle of morality?

  • Reread the groundwork and we'll try to answer that question next time.

Now we turn

字幕と単語

ワンタップで英和辞典検索 単語をクリックすると、意味が表示されます

B1 中級

マイケル・サンデル ジャスティス What's the Right Thing To Do Episode 06 MIND YOUR MOTIVE (Michael Sandel Justice What's The Right Thing To Do Episode 06 MIND YOUR MOTIVE)

  • 142 15
    ares Y に公開 2021 年 01 月 14 日
動画の中の単語