Placeholder Image

字幕表 動画を再生する

  • The connection between philosophy and the mathematical sciences has always been very

  • close. Plato had written over the door of his academy the words, "Let no one enter here

  • who is ignorant of geometry." It was Aristotle who codified the basic sciences into the categories

  • and gave them the names that we use to this day. Some of the greatest philosophers have

  • been themselves great mathematicians who invented new branches of mathematics. Descartes is

  • an obvious example, and so is Leibniz and Pascal.

  • In fact, most of the great philosophers, not all but most, came to philosophy from mathematics

  • or the sciences. And this tendency is continued into our present century. Bertrand Russell

  • was trained first as a mathematician, Wittgenstein was trained first as an engineer. The reason

  • for this persisting connection is, I think, obvious. And that is that the basic urge,

  • which has driven most of the greatest philosophers, has been the urge to deepen our understanding

  • of the world and of its structure. And this is also what creative scientists are doing.

  • For most of the past, too, people thought that mathematics was the most indubitable

  • knowledge, as well as being utterly precise and clear, that human beings possessed. So

  • there have always been plenty of philosophers examining mathematics to try and find out

  • what was so special about it, and whether this was something that could be applied to

  • the acquisition of other sorts of knowledge. Ditto with the sciences, which were also thought

  • to yield a very specially safe and certain kind of knowledge.

  • What was it about science that made its results so reliable, people ask themselves. And could

  • its methods, whatever these were, be used in other fields? These investigations into

  • the concepts, and methods, and procedures, and models that are involved in mathematics

  • and in science have come to be known as the philosophy of mathematics and the philosophy

  • of science. And it's with these that we're going to be concerned in this program. Chiefly

  • with the philosophy of science, though, in fact, we have someone taking part who is expert

  • in both-- Professor Hilary Putnam of Harvard University

  • Professor Putnam, I'd like to start our discussion from a standpoint which I think a very large

  • number of our viewers occupy anyway. And it's really this-- since the 17th century, I suppose,

  • there's been a spectacular decline in religious belief, especially in the West, and especially

  • among educated people. And for millions, the role that used to be taken in life by a world

  • view based on religion has been increasingly supplanting by a world view based on science

  • or, at least, purporting to be derived from science, anyway. And this is still enormously

  • powerful, and the hold that it has on people's minds throughout the West probably affects

  • all of us. So I think I'd like to start this discussion by getting you to pin down that

  • scientific world outlook which is so influential in the modern world and which will be underlying

  • a lot of what we're going to have to talk about.

  • Let me dodge the question a little bit by talking not about what scientists think now

  • but what many scientists thought 100 years ago, or 75 years ago. Think of doing a crossword

  • puzzle. You might have to change a few things as you go along. But towards the end everything

  • fits, and things get added on one step at a time. That's the way the progress of science

  • looked for 300 years.

  • In 1900, a famous mathematician, David Hilbert, gave a list of 50 mathematical problems to

  • a world congress of mathematicians, which are still very famous. And it's very interesting

  • that he included one problem which we would not call a mathematical problem, very early

  • in the list. I think it's problem three, which was to put the foundations of physics on a

  • satisfactory basis.

  • Just a small task. And that was for mathematicians.

  • That was for mathematicians, not for physicists. The ideas--

  • Tidy it up.

  • That's right. The ideas is, Newton, Maxwell, Dalton, and so on had all put in all the parts

  • of the story. And now it was just for mathematicians to, basically, clean up the logic, as it were.

  • I think, in a conversation we had a couple of days ago, you described this as a treasure

  • chest to you. And I like that picture. Here's this big chest that we're just filling up.

  • It's an accumulation, and you don't have to subtract, you don't have to take out. Occasionally

  • you make a little mistake, but basically the idea is-- when you shift the metaphor, like

  • building a pyramid. You put down the ground floor, then the next floor, then the next

  • floor. It just goes up. That's part of it. The view of knowledge as growing by accumulation.

  • The other part of it is the idea that the special success of the sciences-- and obviously

  • what we're impressed by is success. This culture values success and science is a successful

  • institution. But there is the idea that science owes its success to using a special method.

  • And that comes probably from history of science. From the fact that Newton, for example, lived

  • after Bacon, was influenced by Bacon. And the idea that empirical science has grown

  • up together with something called inductive logic. And this idea that there's a method,

  • the inductive method, and that the sciences can be characterized by the fact that they

  • use this method and use it explicitly and consciously as it were-- not, unconsciously

  • as maybe someone who's learning cooking might be using it. But pretty deliberately and explicitly.

  • So I think that these two things-- the idea of knowledge as growing by accumulation and

  • growing by the use of a special method, the inductive method, are the key elements of

  • the old view.

  • Yes and if I were going to put the same thing, I suppose, slightly differently I think I'd

  • say this. For 200 or 300 years, educated Western man thought of the universe, and everything

  • in it as consisting of matter in motion. And that was all there was, whether from the outermost

  • galaxies of the stars into ourselves, and our bodies, and the cells of which we made

  • up, and so on. And that science was finding out more and more about this matter, and its

  • structure, and its motion by a method which you just characterized-- the scientific method.

  • And the idea was that, if we went on long enough, we'd simply-- as you said we do a

  • crossword puzzle metaphor-- we'd find out everything there was to fine out. We could,

  • eventually, by scientific methods completely explain and understand the world. Now that

  • has been abandoned by scientists, hasn't it, though in fact this hasn't got through yet

  • to the non-scientists. There are still large numbers of non-scientists who go on thinking

  • that that's how scientists think. But of course they no longer do, do they. I mean this is

  • starting to break down.

  • I think it's started to break down. I think it started to break down with Einstein. If

  • I can drag in a bit of history of philosophy, screaming, by the hair-- Kant did something

  • in philosophy which I think has begun to happen now in science. He challenged a certain view

  • of truth. Before Kant, no philosopher really doubted that truth was simply correspondence

  • to reality. I mean, there are different words, some philosophers spoke of agreement. But

  • the idea is a mirror theory of knowledge.

  • Today, I think-- well, Kant said it isn't so simple. There's a contribution of the thinking

  • mind. Sure, it isn't made up by the mind. Kant was no idealist. It isn't all a fiction.

  • It isn't something we make up. But it isn't just a copy, either. What we call truth depends

  • both on what there is, on the way things are, and on the contribution of the thinker, the

  • mind.

  • I think that, today, scientists have come to a somewhat similar view. That since the

  • beginning of the 20th century, the idea that there's a human contribution, a mental contribution,

  • to what we call truth, that theories aren't simply dictated to us by the facts, as it

  • were.

  • I'd like to ask you to unpack that a little because I think that some of our viewers will

  • find idea a little puzzling. "How can be," some people will ask themselves, that "what

  • is and is not true can depend not only on what the facts are but on the human mind.

  • How can that be."

  • Well, let me use an analogy with vision. We tend to think that's what we see just depends

  • on what's out there. But the more one studies vision, either as a scientist or as a painter,

  • one discovers that what's called vision involves an enormous amount of interpretation. The

  • color we see as red is not the same color, in terms of wavelengths, at different times

  • of the day. So that even in what we think of as our simplest transaction with the world,

  • just looking at it, we are interpreting. You know--

  • In other words we bring a whole number of things to the world that we're not directly

  • conscious of, usually, unless we turn inwards and start examining them.

  • That's right. I think the world must've looked different in the Middle Ages to someone who

  • looked up and thought of the stars as up and us at the bottom, for example. Today, when

  • we look out into space, I think we have a different experience than somebody with the

  • medieval world view.

  • And what you're saying is that the very categories in which we see the world and interpret our

  • experience, and the ideas within which we organize our observations and the facts around

  • us and such, are provided by us. So that the world as conceived by science is partly contributed

  • by external facts but also partly contributed by categories and ways of seeing things which

  • come from the human observer.

  • That's right. And an example of that in science-- I'll oversimplify, but it's not basically

  • falsified-- is this wave/particle business. It's not that there's something, an electron,

  • which is somehow half a wave and half a particle-- that would be meaningless-- but that there

  • are many experiments which can be described two ways. You can either think of the electron

  • as a wave, or you can think of it as a particle. And both descriptions are, in some crazy way,

  • true and adequate.

  • They're alternative ways of describing the same fact, and both descriptions are accurate.

  • That's right. Philosophies have started talking of equivalent descriptions. It's a term used

  • in philosophy of science.

  • But now, for a couple of hundred years after Newton, educated Weston man thought that what

  • Newton had produced was objective fact. That he had discovered laws which governed the

  • workings of the world and the workings of the universe. And this was just objectively

  • true independently of us. That Newton and other scientists had read these facts off

  • of nature by observing it, and looking at it, and so on. And these statements, which

  • made up science, were simply true.

  • Now, there came, didn't there, a period in the development of science, beginning in the

  • late 19th century, when people began to realize that these statements were not entirely true,

  • that this wasn't just a body of objective fact which had been read off from the world.

  • In other words, that science was corrigible. Scientific theories could be wrong. And that

  • raises some very profound questions. I mean, if science isn't just an objectively true

  • description of the way things are, what is it? And if we don't get it from observing

  • the world, where do we get it from?

  • Well, I don't want to say we don't get it from observing the world at all. Obviously,

  • part of this Kantian image is that there is a contribution which is not us. There's something

  • out there. But that also there's a contribution from us. And even Kant, by the way, thought

  • that Newtonian science was indubitable. in fact we thought we contributed its indubitability.

  • The step beyond Kant is the idea that not only is reality partly mind dependent, but

  • that there are alternatives. And that the concepts we impose on the world may not be

  • the right ones, and we may have to change them. That there's an interaction between

  • what we contribute and what we find out.

  • Now what was it that made people begin to realize that this basic conception of science

  • as objective truth was wrong. That science was corrigible. That science was fallible.

  • I think it's that the older science turned out to be wrong where no one expected it to

  • be wrong. Not in detail, but in the big picture. It's not that we find out that, say, the sun

  • isn't 93 million miles from the earth but only 20 million miles from the earth. That's

  • not going to happen. I mean sometimes one makes blunders even about things like that.

  • But that's like making a blunder about whether there's a chair in the room. Wholesale skepticism

  • about whether numerical values are right in science would be as unjustified as wholesale

  • skepticism about anything.

  • But where the newer theories don't agree with Newton is not over the approximate truth of

  • the mathematical expressions in Newton's theory. Those are still perfectly good for calculation.

  • It's over the big picture. We've replaced the picture of an absolute space and an absolute

  • time by the picture of a four dimensional space time. We replaced a picture of a Euclidean

  • world by a picture of a world which obeys a geometry Euclid never dreamed of. We've

  • swung back to the picture of the word as having a beginning in time, which is really a shocker.

  • It's not even that things once refuted stay refuted forever.

  • So it means, really, that a whole conception of science has been superseded. Instead of

  • thinking of science as a body of knowledge which is being added to all the time by further

  • scientific work, that whole conception of science has in dispensed with, really, hasn't

  • it? And we now think of it as a set of theories which are themselves constantly being replaced

  • by better theories, by more accurate theories, by richer, more explanatory theories. And

  • even the theories we now have, like those of Einstein and his successors, will probably

  • be replaced, in the course of time, by other, better theories by scientists yet unknown.

  • Isn't that so?

  • That's exactly right in fact scientists themselves make this prediction. That is that the main

  • theories of the 20th century-- relativity and quantum mechanics-- will give way to some

  • other theory which will interpret both of them, and so on forever.

  • Now this raises a very fundamental question-- namely, the question, what is truth? I mean,

  • when we say that this or that scientific statement is true, or this or that scientific theory

  • is true, what, in these newly understood circumstances of ours, can we mean by truth?

  • There's still two views that have been since Kant. One is that this old correspondence

  • view still has its adherents. But I think the view that's coming in more and more is

  • that one cannot make a total separation between what's true and what our standards of assertibility

  • are. That the way in which the-- what I call using the Kantian picture-- the mind-dependence

  • of truth comes in is the fact that what's true and what's false is in part a function

  • of what our standards of truth and falsity are.

  • And that depends on our interests, which, again, change over time, of course.

  • That's right

  • I'd like you to say a little more about this question of truth because this again, I think,

  • is puzzling to the layman. I think that people who are not trained in science or philosophy

  • are apt to think that there are a certain set of facts, and a true statement is a statement

  • that accurately describes those facts. I'd like to talk a little about some of the difficulties

  • that are actually involved in this.

  • I think the biggest difficulty in science itself comes from the fact that, even within

  • one scientific theory, you often find different accounts can be given the so-called facts.

  • This came in with the special theory of relativity, when it turned out that facts about simultaneity,

  • where the two things happen at the same time, could be described differently by different

  • observers. One could say "Boy Scout A fired a starter's pistol before Boy Scout B," the

  • other could say, "No, Boy Scout B fired a starter's pistol before Boy Scout A," and

  • if the distance is sufficiently large, so that a light signal can't travel from one

  • to the other without exceeding the speed of light, then it may be both descriptions are

  • correct. Both are admissible.

  • Of course, this leads to profound conceptual difficulties in understanding some modern

  • scientific theories. And this prompts the thought that a scientific theory can be useful,

  • and meaningful, and can work even if nobody really quite understands what it means. And

  • this is the case with quantum mechanics, isn't it? I mean, nobody is really sure what quantum

  • mechanics actually means, and yet it works.

  • That's right and, again, I want to say one shouldn't push that too far. Because I think

  • we don't want to give up our standards of intelligibility altogether. We want to say--

  • quantum mechanics works, and the very fact that it works means that there's something

  • fundamentally right about it. And with respect to its intelligibility, we're willing to say,

  • in part, that may be that we have the wrong standards of intelligibility, that we have

  • to change our intuitions. But in part, there are real paradoxes in the theory. And I think

  • that's more work has to be done to really get a satisfactory resolution of these paradoxes.

  • Things are very ticklish now.

  • Yes, I think somebody hearing our discussion to whom, perhaps, some of these ideas are

  • new might find himself thinking-- well, if all this is so, how is it that science works?

  • If traditional scientific theories are breaking down, if science is turning out not to be

  • a body of reliable, permanent, firm, objective knowledge, if a significant portion of every

  • scientific theory is subjective anyway, in the sense that it's contributed by the human

  • mind, by the observed by the scientists, how is it, in these circumstances, that we can

  • actually build bridges, fly airplanes, make rockets go to the moon, and actually make

  • all this soft fuzzy changing partly subjective body of theory work for us. It must fit the

  • world, in some very basic way, in spite of everything that we've been saying.

  • That's true, but I think the contrast between being subjective and fitting the world isn't

  • altogether right. I'm not saying that scientific knowledge is subjective, or that anything

  • goes. I say we're in the difficult position that we often are in in life of thinking there

  • is a difference we good and bad reasoning but we don't have a mechanical rule.

  • In everyday life we use interest-loaded terms. We wouldn't say that there's a policeman on

  • the corner if we didn't have a whole network of social institutions. Somebody coming from

  • a primitive tribe which didn't have policemen might say there's a man in blue on the corner.

  • But the fact that the notion of a policeman is shaped by our interest doesn't mean that

  • it can't be objectively true that there's a policeman on the corner.

  • Also, I think science works precisely because of this corrigibility, in large part, as Professor

  • Poppers pointed out. The difference between science and previous ways of trying to find

  • out truth is in large part that scientists are willing to test their ideas because they

  • don't regard them as infallible. In a way, that was known at the beginning, and then

  • in the success of Newtonian science, somewhat forgotten. And we've had to be reminded again

  • of what Bacon knew-- that you have to put questions to nature and be willing to change

  • your ideas if they don't work.

  • In some respects, the traditional opposition between science and religion has-- the two

  • parties have crossed places, haven't they? I mean, many religious people now believe

  • they have certain knowledge about the world-- that it was created by called a god, that

  • he made us in his own image, gave us immortal souls which will survive out there, and so

  • on. Certain very fundamental propositions which they hold with absolute certainty. And

  • it's the scientist who believes that everything is fallible, that the world is a mysterious

  • place that we'll never get to the end of the mystery of, and so on and so forth. Isn't

  • there something in that?

  • Maybe.

  • You say it maybe?

  • I'm not sure.

  • You're not sure. Well let's not pursue that. But one point I do want to take up with you,

  • leaving even religion aside, is that now science is seen in this entirely different way that

  • you've been describing, by virtually all scientists, doesn't it mean that the difference between

  • science and non-science isn't what it was always thought of as being. In other words,

  • since science is so subjective, indefinite, changing, and so on it's no longer a clearly-cut

  • and different kind of human activity, and kind of human knowledge, from other sorts

  • of human knowledge and other sorts of human activity.

  • I think that's both true and culturally very important. I think the harm that the old picture

  • of science does is that if there is this realm of absolute fact that scientists are gradually

  • accumulating then everything else appears, somehow, as non-knowledge, something to which

  • even words like true and false can't properly apply. I think that the so-called fact-value

  • dichotomy is a very good example of this. It's hard to have a discussion, on politics

  • for example, without someone very quickly say, at least in my country, is that a fact

  • or a value judgment. As though it can't be a fact that Hitler was a bad man, for example,

  • or a factory that Farah Fawcett Majors is a beautiful woman.

  • And do you think that it is a fact that Hitler was a bad man?

  • Oh yes, I do.

  • I do too.

  • But then, if this is so, if we're abandoning so many of these comfortable, clear-cut, distinctions

  • of the past, what's the point of continuing to use the category, or the notion or the

  • term "science" anyway? I mean, does it any longer clearly demarcate something differentiable

  • from everything else.

  • I don't think it does. I think that-- if you're going to distinguish science from non-science--

  • that makes a lot of sense if you still have this old view that there's this inductive

  • method. What make something science is that it uses it and uses it pretty consciously

  • and pretty deliberately. And that what makes something non-science is, either it uses it

  • entirety unconsciously, as in learning how to cook-- you're not consciously thinking

  • about inductive logic, or perhaps doesn't use it at all, as metaphysics was alleged

  • not to use it all, I think unfairly.

  • But both say that there's a sharp line between, say, practical knowledge and science. And

  • to say that the method which is supposed to draw this line is rather fuzzy, something

  • that we can state exactly-- and attempts to state it, by the way, have been very much

  • a failure, still. Inductive logic cannot be, say, programmed on a computer the way deductive

  • logic can be programmed on a computer. And I think the development of deductive logic

  • in the last 100 years and the development of the computer have really brought very dramatically

  • just what a different state we are in with respect to proof in the mathematical sciences,

  • which we can state rigorous canons for, and proof in what used to be called the inductive

  • sciences, where we can state general maxims, but you really have to use intuition, general

  • know-how, and so on in applying them.

  • One of the two categories that you described the old-fashioned way of looking at science

  • in terms of was that there was a particular scientific method. That you observed the facts,

  • and, on the basis of these observed instances, you generalized to form scientific theories

  • which you then verified by experiment, and so on. That was the old view. Now that that

  • has been abandoned, is there any longer any single method which is thought of as being

  • scientific method?

  • I don't think they should be. People talk of scientific method as a sort of fiction.

  • But I think that, even in physics where you do get experiments and tests which pretty

  • much fit the textbooks, there's a great deal that doesn't and a great deal that shouldn't.

  • And I think, in fact, in the culture I don't really believe there's an agreement on what

  • a science and what isn't. Any university will tell you in its catalog that there are things

  • called social sciences and that sociology is as science, and that economics is a science.

  • I bet if you ask anyone in the physics department whether sociology is a science, he'll say

  • no.

  • And why will he say no? That's interesting.

  • I think the real reason is not that the sociologists don't use the inductive method. They probably

  • use it more conscientiously, poor things, than the physicists do. I think it's because

  • they're not as successful.

  • So you know that science has become almost a name for successful pursuit of knowledge?

  • That's right.

  • Well now, I think you've given a very, very good description of the way in which these

  • age-old view of what science was has broken down in our century and been replaced by something

  • much more fluid and perhaps much more difficult to get hold of. But you have, I think, described

  • it very clearly. Can we now come, against, this background to what philosophers of science

  • are actually doing. You are a philosopher of science, what do you and your colleagues

  • do.

  • Well, part of what we do which I won't try to describe on this broadcast is fairly technical

  • investigation of specific scientific theories. We look at quantum mechanics very closely.

  • Both to learn what lessons we can from it for philosophy and to see what contributions

  • we can make as philosophers to clarifying its foundations. We look at relativity theory

  • very closely. We look at Darwinian evolution very closely, and so on. This is the part

  • of philosophy of science which provides the data for the rest.

  • But much philosophy of sciences shades over into general philosophy. And I think that

  • the best way to describe it is in terms of what we've been talking about. That is, each

  • of the issues we've been talking about divides philosophers of science.

  • There are philosophers of science who have a correspondence view of truth and try to

  • show that this can be made precise, that the objections can be overcome, you can still

  • view science, somehow, in the old way. And there are others who try to sketch what another

  • view of truth would come to. There are philosophers who still think there is an inductive method

  • that can be rigorously stated and who work on inductive logic. And by the way, I think

  • it's important there should be because we won't make progress to trying to state the

  • inductive method if there aren't.

  • And that there are others who view the development of science more culturally, more historically,

  • and then people like myself who are have a sort of in-between position. That there's

  • something to the notion of a scientific method, there are clear examples, but that it's more

  • or less a continuum. That you mustn't think of it as a kind of mechanical rule, an algorithm,

  • that you can apply to get scientific knowledge. So that I'd say each of these issues-- the

  • nature of truth, the nature of the scientific method, whether there's any necessary truth

  • in science, any conceptual contribution which is permanent and can't be subject to revision

  • is a big question

  • And who are you-- plural-- doing all this work for? I don't ask that in an irreverent

  • way but what I have in mind is this. I've myself taken part in attempts to bring scientists

  • and philosophers together for discussions of precisely the issues that you've raised.

  • And these attempts have usually failed and failed to the same reason-- namely, that the

  • scientists lose interest. They go back to their laboratories and get on with doing more

  • science. And the great bulk of scientists, it seems to me, don't, in fact, take very

  • much of an interest in the issues that you've been talking about.

  • I think it's conspicuous that the greatest of all scientists are exceptions. I mean,

  • the really block-busting, the path-breaking scientists who've actually made the revolution

  • in this century that you've been talking about-- people like Einstein, Max Planck, Neils Bohr,

  • Max Born, Schrodinger, de Broglie, these people were enormously interested in the conceptual

  • questions that's you've raise. But these were the pioneering geniuses. And the great mass

  • of thousands of scientists, who follow on behind them and put their work to its practical

  • application, they don't seem to care so who is listening to you, who is reading the stuff

  • that you publish?

  • Well, I'd say first of all I think we are basically writing for the philosophically-interested

  • layman, for the reader of philosophy. I don't view philosophy of science as giving direct

  • advice to scientists, just as I think more philosophers are ill-advised to think that

  • they're giving, at least, immediately current contemporary advice on how to live your life

  • or what bills to pass in parliament.

  • On the other hand, I do think it's scientists tend to know the philosophy of science of

  • 50 years ago. And perhaps this isn't a bad thing. That is, perhaps this time lag, this

  • culture lag has some value in weeding out what they shouldn't pay attention to. And

  • it's annoying to a philosopher to encounter a scientist who's both sure that he needn't

  • listen to any philosophy of science, and then who produces verbatim ideas which you can

  • recognize as coming from what was popular in 1928.

  • Is there a direct parallel here between what you're saying about scientists and the economist

  • Keynes' famous remark that nearly all businessman who thought they were indifferent to airy-fairy

  • economic theory were in fact the slaves of the economic theorists of yesterday, of a

  • previous generation.

  • That's exactly true.

  • I suppose another parallel one could make would be to say that the account that ordinary

  • language-users give of language, and their use of language, would be extremely unsophisticated

  • simply because they take it for granted and have never thought about it. That too would

  • probably apply to the account that most scientists would give of what they were doing when they

  • were doing their science.

  • That's right. That is, it's a mistake to think that merely because one practices an activity

  • one can give a theory of it.

  • One criticism that's often been made about philosopher of science is that although they

  • talk of science in this general way, what they're nearly always referring to, in fact,

  • is one science namely physics. Now it's true, isn't it, that the science in which the most

  • exciting developments have probably taken place in the last 20 years, anyway, has been

  • not physics but biology. Are philosophers of science open, genuinely open, to the criticism

  • of being too physics-based in their view of science and having ignored biology too much?

  • I think I would defend us against that on the grounds that I don't-- although the theories

  • in biology are of great scientific importance-- Darwin's theory of evolution, Crick/Watson

  • on DNA, and so on they don't, by and large, pose big methodological problems of a kind

  • of don't arise in physical science. I mean, I'm not sure whether you're going to agree

  • with that.

  • Well, I mean, you mentioned evolution just now. And it seems to me that here is a concept

  • which originated in one of the sciences, namely biology, and which, over a comparatively short

  • period of time, has spread throughout the whole of our culture. So the way almost everybody

  • think is influenced by the notion of evolution. Not only about the origins of man but about

  • institutions, or the arts, all kinds of other things. I mean, evolution has become a dimension

  • of Western man's thinking about almost anything. Is that not so?

  • That's right and perhaps there has not been enough attention to this theory. Though what

  • strikes me as interesting is that the possibility of explanations of what we think of as the

  • biological kind-- explanations in terms of function, rather than in terms of physics

  • and chemistry, what you're made have come under more attention, recently, as a result

  • of computer science.

  • Now, this does raise something I'm particularly interested in when you talk of computer Science

  • And that is the interaction between our technology, in the case of computers, and philosophy.

  • Not just science and philosophy, but technology and philosophy. I mean, computers were originally

  • constructed on the basis of a self-conscious analogy with the human mind. But as they became

  • more and more sophisticated we began to learn things from them about the human mind. So

  • our construction of computers and what they, then, tell us about ourselves seems to actually

  • proceed by interactive growth. Isn't that so?

  • That's right, and today this is one are, by the way, in which philosophers are in close

  • contact with scientists. That is, the fields of linguistics, cognitive psychology, computer

  • science, philosophy of language, today, interact constantly. People send papers to one another--

  • not because someone tells them to. There are conferences at which specialists needs to

  • meet together-- again, not because someone decided there should be some cross-fertilization.

  • The interesting thing about the computer case, if I can stick with it for a moment, is, one

  • might have thought that the rise of the computer would encourage a certain kind of vulgar materialism.

  • That is, "so, after all, we are machines. So, after all, everything about us can be

  • explained in terms of physics and chemistry." Paradoxically the real effect of the computer

  • on psychology on philosophy of mind has been a decrease in that kind of reductionism.

  • See the thing about the computer is that when you work with computers you very rarely have

  • to think about their physics and chemistry. There's a distinction that people draw between

  • their software-- meaning their program, their instructions, their rules, the way they do

  • things-- and their hardware. And generally, you ignore their hardware. You talk about

  • computers at the software level. And you wouldn't really be able to explain what they do, in

  • a way that would be if any use to anyone, in terms at the hardware level.

  • There is a kind of emergence here-- although it's not a mystical kind of emergence, it's

  • not that they're violating the laws of physics-- it's just that the level of organization,

  • that higher-level facts about organization have a kind of autonomy. You'd say this, the

  • fact that it's following this program explains why does this, and I don't need to know how

  • it's built. I only need to know it can be built in such a way that will follow this

  • program.

  • This is a return to view and-- if you apply this to the mind-- it suggests a return to

  • view of mind that I associate with Aristotle. It's the view that we are not ghosts in a

  • machine, not spirits which only temporarily in bodies, but that the relation between the

  • mind in the body is a relation of function to what has that function. Aristotle said,

  • "if you use the word soul in connection with an axe-- and of course," he said, "you don't--

  • you'd say the soul of an axe is cutting." And he said, "the soul of the eye is seeing."

  • And he thought of man as "a thing that thinks."

  • You're talking, now, of the alternative to materialism and, say, a religious view that

  • this gives us. Puts me in mind, instantly, of the most significant of all the materialist

  • philosophers in the modern world-- namely Marxism. Which, after all, is the official

  • state philosophy of about a third of mankind as we sit here discussing this. Marxism claims

  • to be scientific, and this is a very important thing about it. Is there a significant Marxist

  • contribution to the philosophy of science?

  • I don't think there's a significant Marxist contribution. But I don't think that the Marxist

  • were all wrong either. I think Engles was one of the most scientifically learned men

  • of his century. He got a number of things wrong. But he had an immense general scientific

  • knowledge.

  • And Anti-Duhring, his big book on philosophy of science-- although it contains some rather

  • strange ideas, some of which he gets from Hegel, by the way-- is, on the whole, a sensible

  • book on philosophy of science, among other things. On the other hand, it's not specifically

  • Marxist. I'd say that Engles views on philosophy of science are, in large part, influenced

  • by the standard philosophy of science of the time. They're a fairly sophisticated inductive

  • account.

  • And what about subsequent Marxist thinkers who also had some pretension to be philosophers.

  • Like Lenin, for example.

  • Well, I think they're uneven. Lenin, I think, is one of the worst. He says, for example,

  • that theories are copies of motion. And there you have the copy theory, of science just

  • copying off the reality, in its crudest view. Mao is more sophisticated. Mao is very influenced

  • by John Dewey, who was widely read in China in the 1920s.

  • Do you think it's actually made contribution to the subject as it is today, or not really?

  • I think that it anticipated-- it perhaps might have made a contribution if people have been

  • less ideologically divided. Because I think non-Marx's could have learned-- the Marxists

  • were among the first people to try to, somehow, combine a realist view with a stress on practice,

  • with the stress on corrigibility. And they were very hostile to the notion a priori truth.

  • And today many mainline philosophers of science are very hostile to a priori truth.

  • As it is, they play some of the role in philosophy of science, I think, that Keynes said they

  • play in economics. He described Marx as one of his, sort of, underground predecessors.

  • [LAUGHTER]

  • When I was introducing this program I mentioned not only the philosophy of science but also

  • the philosophy of mathematics. And before we close, I would like us to say something

  • about that anyway. I suppose one can really say that the central problem in the philosophy

  • of mathematics is a direct parallel to the central problem in the philosophy of science--

  • namely, how long does it fit the world? With science it's-- how does science fit the world?

  • In mathematics it's how does mathematics fit the world. is that right?

  • That's right. And it's even worse. Because if you're trying to defend a copy view, a

  • correspondence of view , of truth in empirical science, you can answer the question-- well

  • how do we build up this picture in such a way that it corresponds by saying we have

  • sense organs. As I mentioned before that's not a total answer because there's a tremendous

  • amount of interpretation involved in simple seeing and simple hearing. But if you are

  • talking about numbers and sets, and somebody says, OK, if mathematical knowledge is simply

  • some kind of a copy of the way numbers are, and the way sets are, and the way other abstract

  • objects that mathematicians study are, the question then, what sense enables us to see

  • how they--

  • Yes, what is a number. Yes, yes. A deeply problematic question but still an important

  • one.

  • That's right. And on the other hand, I don't want to say that the anti-correspondence has

  • it very easy either. It seems to me that mathematical knowledge is a real puzzle. And I think that

  • philosophers should concentrate more on philosophy of mathematics than they do now because it

  • seems to be an area where no theory works very well.

  • Isn't there another very important parallel between mathematics and science. I mean, throughout

  • the history of science one of the conflicts has been between one camp who thought that

  • it was all about objects in the world which existed independent of human experience and

  • another camp which thought, no, it's human beings and observers who actually contribute

  • most of this. And as you pointed out much earlier discussion, the truth is almost certainly

  • a combination of both. There is a longstanding dispute in mathematics, isn't there, between

  • one body of people who think that mathematical knowledge is something that's, so to speak,

  • inherent in the structure of the world, and we derive it from the world by experience

  • and observation, and another body of mathematical thought that says-- no, no, no, mathematics

  • is a creation of the human mind which we then try to impose on reality like a grid, as it

  • was, on a landscape. Isn't that so?

  • That's right. The latter story's attractive because of the sense organ problem but it

  • doesn't seem to work either because it seems that we're not free to impose any mathematics

  • or any logic we want. Almost anyone would admit that, at least, you have to be consistent.

  • And what's consistent and what isn't somehow something we can just make up or decide. When

  • we try to stress conventionalist accounts, subjective accounts, we come up against the

  • objectivity of mathematics. When we try to stress the objectivity of mathematics we come

  • up against another set of problems. I think we can learn a lot more than we now know about

  • human knowledge and about scientific knowledge by going further into this area.

  • Talking of where we're going from where we are, so to speak, I think the most interesting

  • way in which you could end this discussion, Professor Putnam, would be by talking about

  • what you regard as the most interesting problem areas of the moment. And therefore, I take

  • it, the most-likely growth area for the immediate future in both of the subjects we've been

  • discussing-- philosophy of science and philosophy of mathematics.

  • OK, I think that if I'm allowed to confine my prediction to the immediate future-- because

  • we know that long-run predictions are always false. But in the immediate future, I would

  • expect philosophy of mathematics to be a growth area, and philosophy of logic. I would expect

  • philosophy of physics, I think, to decline somewhat from its central place in philosophy

  • of science. Although I think that part of it touches philosophy of logic.

  • The astounding suggestion has actually come forward in connection with quantum mechanics

  • that we may have to change our logic, our view of what the true logical laws are in

  • order to really understand how the world can be quantum mechanical. I think this side a

  • philosophy of quantum mechanics that touches philosophy of logic will be a hot discussion

  • area. But more generally, I think areas which we almost don't think of this philosophy of

  • science, that become philosophy of language and philosophy of mind, like these questions

  • about computer models of the mind, computer models of language, and these more general

  • questions about theories of truth, the nature of truth, the nature of verification, how

  • science can be objective even though there's not a rigorous scientific method-- I think

  • these questions will continue to be the staples of the field.

  • One thing that worries me about this whole area is its relationship to the educated layman

  • which, in a sense, is the person our discussion has been for. After all, it's not over the

  • 70 years since the 25-year-old Einstein published the theory of relativity. And I'm sure you

  • agree with me that it's true to say now that the great majority of educating people with

  • higher education, university degrees and so on, still have scarcely any idea of what this

  • is all about. And it's done very little to actually influence their view of the world.

  • Isn't there a danger that now science and mathematics are simply racing ahead. And the

  • whole new range and world of insight that is giving us into the universe in which we

  • live simply isn't filtering through to the non-specialist or not filtering through anything

  • like fast enough.

  • That is a danger, but it's one that something can be done about. There's now, for example,

  • a text of special relativity, called space time physics, which is designed for the first

  • month of the first freshman college physics course. And the authors say, at the beginning,

  • that they look forward to the time when it will be taught in high schools. And do think

  • that time will, in fact, come, and quite soon?

  • Oh, I'm sure of it.

  • Yes, well I think you're right. And indeed, I hope you are. Thank you very much Professor

  • Putnam.

  • Thank you.

The connection between philosophy and the mathematical sciences has always been very

字幕と単語

ワンタップで英和辞典検索 単語をクリックすると、意味が表示されます

B1 中級

科学哲学についてのヒラリー・パットナム (1977) (Hilary Putnam on the Philosophy of Science (1977))

  • 52 7
    songwen8778 に公開 2021 年 01 月 14 日
動画の中の単語