Placeholder Image

字幕表 動画を再生する

  • The connection between philosophy and the mathematical sciences has always been very

  • close. Plato had written over the door of his academy the words, "Let no one enter here

  • who is ignorant of geometry." It was Aristotle who codified the basic sciences into the categories

  • and gave them the names that we use to this day. Some of the greatest philosophers have

  • been themselves great mathematicians who invented new branches of mathematics. Descartes is

  • an obvious example, and so is Leibniz and Pascal.

  • In fact, most of the great philosophers, not all but most, came to philosophy from mathematics

  • or the sciences. And this tendency is continued into our present century. Bertrand Russell

  • was trained first as a mathematician, Wittgenstein was trained first as an engineer. The reason

  • for this persisting connection is, I think, obvious. And that is that the basic urge,

  • which has driven most of the greatest philosophers, has been the urge to deepen our understanding

  • of the world and of its structure. And this is also what creative scientists are doing.

  • For most of the past, too, people thought that mathematics was the most indubitable

  • knowledge, as well as being utterly precise and clear, that human beings possessed. So

  • there have always been plenty of philosophers examining mathematics to try and find out

  • what was so special about it, and whether this was something that could be applied to

  • the acquisition of other sorts of knowledge. Ditto with the sciences, which were also thought

  • to yield a very specially safe and certain kind of knowledge.

  • What was it about science that made its results so reliable, people ask themselves. And could

  • its methods, whatever these were, be used in other fields? These investigations into

  • the concepts, and methods, and procedures, and models that are involved in mathematics

  • and in science have come to be known as the philosophy of mathematics and the philosophy

  • of science. And it's with these that we're going to be concerned in this program. Chiefly

  • with the philosophy of science, though, in fact, we have someone taking part who is expert

  • in both-- Professor Hilary Putnam of Harvard University

  • Professor Putnam, I'd like to start our discussion from a standpoint which I think a very large

  • number of our viewers occupy anyway. And it's really this-- since the 17th century, I suppose,

  • there's been a spectacular decline in religious belief, especially in the West, and especially

  • among educated people. And for millions, the role that used to be taken in life by a world

  • view based on religion has been increasingly supplanting by a world view based on science

  • or, at least, purporting to be derived from science, anyway. And this is still enormously

  • powerful, and the hold that it has on people's minds throughout the West probably affects

  • all of us. So I think I'd like to start this discussion by getting you to pin down that

  • scientific world outlook which is so influential in the modern world and which will be underlying

  • a lot of what we're going to have to talk about.

  • Let me dodge the question a little bit by talking not about what scientists think now

  • but what many scientists thought 100 years ago, or 75 years ago. Think of doing a crossword

  • puzzle. You might have to change a few things as you go along. But towards the end everything

  • fits, and things get added on one step at a time. That's the way the progress of science

  • looked for 300 years.

  • In 1900, a famous mathematician, David Hilbert, gave a list of 50 mathematical problems to

  • a world congress of mathematicians, which are still very famous. And it's very interesting

  • that he included one problem which we would not call a mathematical problem, very early

  • in the list. I think it's problem three, which was to put the foundations of physics on a

  • satisfactory basis.

  • Just a small task. And that was for mathematicians.

  • That was for mathematicians, not for physicists. The ideas--

  • Tidy it up.

  • That's right. The ideas is, Newton, Maxwell, Dalton, and so on had all put in all the parts

  • of the story. And now it was just for mathematicians to, basically, clean up the logic, as it were.

  • I think, in a conversation we had a couple of days ago, you described this as a treasure

  • chest to you. And I like that picture. Here's this big chest that we're just filling up.

  • It's an accumulation, and you don't have to subtract, you don't have to take out. Occasionally

  • you make a little mistake, but basically the idea is-- when you shift the metaphor, like

  • building a pyramid. You put down the ground floor, then the next floor, then the next

  • floor. It just goes up. That's part of it. The view of knowledge as growing by accumulation.

  • The other part of it is the idea that the special success of the sciences-- and obviously

  • what we're impressed by is success. This culture values success and science is a successful

  • institution. But there is the idea that science owes its success to using a special method.

  • And that comes probably from history of science. From the fact that Newton, for example, lived

  • after Bacon, was influenced by Bacon. And the idea that empirical science has grown

  • up together with something called inductive logic. And this idea that there's a method,

  • the inductive method, and that the sciences can be characterized by the fact that they

  • use this method and use it explicitly and consciously as it were-- not, unconsciously

  • as maybe someone who's learning cooking might be using it. But pretty deliberately and explicitly.

  • So I think that these two things-- the idea of knowledge as growing by accumulation and

  • growing by the use of a special method, the inductive method, are the key elements of

  • the old view.

  • Yes and if I were going to put the same thing, I suppose, slightly differently I think I'd

  • say this. For 200 or 300 years, educated Western man thought of the universe, and everything

  • in it as consisting of matter in motion. And that was all there was, whether from the outermost

  • galaxies of the stars into ourselves, and our bodies, and the cells of which we made

  • up, and so on. And that science was finding out more and more about this matter, and its

  • structure, and its motion by a method which you just characterized-- the scientific method.

  • And the idea was that, if we went on long enough, we'd simply-- as you said we do a

  • crossword puzzle metaphor-- we'd find out everything there was to fine out. We could,

  • eventually, by scientific methods completely explain and understand the world. Now that

  • has been abandoned by scientists, hasn't it, though in fact this hasn't got through yet

  • to the non-scientists. There are still large numbers of non-scientists who go on thinking

  • that that's how scientists think. But of course they no longer do, do they. I mean this is

  • starting to break down.

  • I think it's started to break down. I think it started to break down with Einstein. If

  • I can drag in a bit of history of philosophy, screaming, by the hair-- Kant did something

  • in philosophy which I think has begun to happen now in science. He challenged a certain view

  • of truth. Before Kant, no philosopher really doubted that truth was simply correspondence

  • to reality. I mean, there are different words, some philosophers spoke of agreement. But

  • the idea is a mirror theory of knowledge.

  • Today, I think-- well, Kant said it isn't so simple. There's a contribution of the thinking

  • mind. Sure, it isn't made up by the mind. Kant was no idealist. It isn't all a fiction.

  • It isn't something we make up. But it isn't just a copy, either. What we call truth depends

  • both on what there is, on the way things are, and on the contribution of the thinker, the

  • mind.

  • I think that, today, scientists have come to a somewhat similar view. That since the

  • beginning of the 20th century, the idea that there's a human contribution, a mental contribution,

  • to what we call truth, that theories aren't simply dictated to us by the facts, as it

  • were.

  • I'd like to ask you to unpack that a little because I think that some of our viewers will

  • find idea a little puzzling. "How can be," some people will ask themselves, that "what

  • is and is not true can depend not only on what the facts are but on the human mind.

  • How can that be."

  • Well, let me use an analogy with vision. We tend to think that's what we see just depends

  • on what's out there. But the more one studies vision, either as a scientist or as a painter,

  • one discovers that what's called vision involves an enormous amount of interpretation. The

  • color we see as red is not the same color, in terms of wavelengths, at different times

  • of the day. So that even in what we think of as our simplest transaction with the world,

  • just looking at it, we are interpreting. You know--

  • In other words we bring a whole number of things to the world that we're not directly

  • conscious of, usually, unless we turn inwards and start examining them.

  • That's right. I think the world must've looked different in the Middle Ages to someone who

  • looked up and thought of the stars as up and us at the bottom, for example. Today, when

  • we look out into space, I think we have a different experience than somebody with the

  • medieval world view.

  • And what you're saying is that the very categories in which we see the world and interpret our

  • experience, and the ideas within which we organize our observations and the facts around

  • us and such, are provided by us. So that the world as conceived by science is partly contributed

  • by external facts but also partly contributed by categories and ways of seeing things which

  • come from the human observer.

  • That's right. And an example of that in science-- I'll oversimplify, but it's not basically

  • falsified-- is this wave/particle business. It's not that there's something, an electron,

  • which is somehow half a wave and half a particle-- that would be meaningless-- but that there

  • are many experiments which can be described two ways. You can either think of the electron

  • as a wave, or you can think of it as a particle. And both descriptions are, in some crazy way,

  • true and adequate.

  • They're alternative ways of describing the same fact, and both descriptions are accurate.

  • That's right. Philosophies have started talking of equivalent descriptions. It's a term used

  • in philosophy of science.

  • But now, for a couple of hundred years after Newton, educated Weston man thought that what

  • Newton had produced was objective fact. That he had discovered laws which governed the

  • workings of the world and the workings of the universe. And this was just objectively

  • true independently of us. That Newton and other scientists had read these facts off

  • of nature by observing it, and looking at it, and so on. And these statements, which

  • made up science, were simply true.

  • Now, there came, didn't there, a period in the development of science, beginning in the

  • late 19th century, when people began to realize that these statements were not entirely true,

  • that this wasn't just a body of objective fact which had been read off from the world.

  • In other words, that science was corrigible. Scientific theories could be wrong. And that

  • raises some very profound questions. I mean, if science isn't just an objectively true

  • description of the way things are, what is it? And if we don't get it from observing

  • the world, where do we get it from?

  • Well, I don't want to say we don't get it from observing the world at all. Obviously,

  • part of this Kantian image is that there is a contribution which is not us. There's something

  • out there. But that also there's a contribution from us. And even Kant, by the way, thought

  • that Newtonian science was indubitable. in fact we thought we contributed its indubitability.

  • The step beyond Kant is the idea that not only is reality partly mind dependent, but

  • that there are alternatives. And that the concepts we impose on the world may not be

  • the right ones, and we may have to change them. That there's an interaction between

  • what we contribute and what we find out.

  • Now what was it that made people begin to realize that this basic conception of science

  • as objective truth was wrong. That science was corrigible. That science was fallible.

  • I think it's that the older science turned out to be wrong where no one expected it to

  • be wrong. Not in detail, but in the big picture. It's not that we find out that, say, the sun

  • isn't 93 million miles from the earth but only 20 million miles from the earth. That's

  • not going to happen. I mean sometimes one makes blunders even about things like that.

  • But that's like making a blunder about whether there's a chair in the room. Wholesale skepticism

  • about whether numerical values are right in science would be as unjustified as wholesale

  • skepticism about anything.

  • But where the newer theories don't agree with Newton is not over the approximate truth of

  • the mathematical