字幕表 動画を再生する 英語字幕をプリント Imagine you are on a distant planet, interacting with an alien species that mirrors human behavior perfectly, yet the species lacks any subjective experience or awareness. This alien species moves and talks like humans do, displaying a rich variety of emotional and social responses. They shake hands, laugh at jokes, and show genuine excitement when discussing their latest achievements. Their world is filled with art, music, and literature, and they participate in social structures that parallel human families and communities. Their behavior is impeccably human-like. However, they lack any inner world of subjective experience or consciousness. These aliens are what philosophers might call "philosophical zombies" or "p-zombies," entities that outwardly appear fully sentient but internally are devoid of awareness or subjective feeling. Despite their advanced behaviors and complex interactions, they are hollow vessels, mere automata going through the motions. This concept highlights a haunting question about the nature of consciousness: how can we ever truly know what lies within another being, and what is it that gives rise to our own rich inner lives? So let's talk about it To delve into the implications of p-zombies, it will be helpful to talk about the hard problem of consciousness. So What is the hard problem of consciousness? The "hard problem of consciousness" is a term coined by philosopher David Chalmers. It addresses the challenge of explaining why and how subjective experiences, or qualia, arise from neural processes. This contrasts with the "easy problems" of consciousness, which deal with understanding the brain's functional aspects, like information processing and behavioral responses. While the term "easy problems" is used somewhat tongue-in-cheek, Chalmers emphasizes that these issues are still quite challenging. As cognitive psychologist Steven Pinker notes, they are "easy" only in comparison to the hard problem. At least For the “easy problem” scientists know what to look for, and with sufficient resources and intellectual effort, solutions might be found within this century. The hard problem, on the other hand, seeks to uncover why these processes are associated with personal, internal experiences, such as the redness of red or the pain of a headache. While science can map brain activity and understand its functions, this problem questions why these processes give rise to a conscious state rather than operating in darkness. It's a philosophical issue that continues to puzzle researchers in neuroscience, cognitive science, and philosophy. This leads us to two predominant theories in the philosophy of mind,Physicalism and Mind-Body Dualism : So What are the differences between Physicalism and Mind-Body Dualism? Physicalism posits that everything is physical or at least supervenes on the physical. Under this view, mental states, including consciousness, are the result of physical interactions within the brain. If true, the exact replication of a human's physical brain state should yield identical conscious experiences, leaving no room for p-zombies—they simply cannot exist because their physical equivalence to humans necessitates consciousness. Mind-Body Dualism, on the other hand, argues that mental phenomena are non-physical and thus, not bound by physical laws. This perspective allows for the possibility of p-zombies as it suggests that physical replication alone might not replicate consciousness. The mental and physical are distinct, and one can exist without the other. These theories bring us to the concept of the philosophical zombie. So What is the philosophical zombie? The Philosophical Zombie Argument is a thought experiment in the philosophy of mind, particularly in discussions about consciousness and physicalism. Proposed by philosopher David Chalmers, the argument presents the concept of a "philosophical zombie," which is an entity that is indistinguishable from a normal human being in every way except that it lacks conscious experience, qualia, or sentience. The zombie behaves and appears exactly like any other human; it can speak about its emotions, respond to pain, and behave as if it is conscious, but it does not actually have any subjective experience. The core of the zombie argument is to challenge physicalism, the doctrine that everything is physical or that the real world consists only of physical entities. Chalmers uses this argument to suggest that conscious experience cannot be fully explained by physical processes alone. If it is conceivable that there could be a physical duplicate of a person without consciousness, then consciousness must involve something non-physical. This leads to the conclusion that physicalism is false, as the existence of such zombies would mean that physical facts do not exhaustively account for mental facts. Chalmers argues that the mere logical possibility of p-zombies suggests that physicalism is insufficient to explain consciousness. If we can coherently conceive of a human devoid of consciousness, then consciousness and the physical brain state cannot be identical. A related thought experiment, known as Mary's Room, further supports this notion. So What is Mary's room thought experiment? The Mary's Room thought experiment, a thought experiment proposed by philosopher Frank Jackson, provides an intriguing insight into the nature of subjective experience. In this scenario, he imagines a scientist named Mary who lives her entire life in a black-and-white room. Despite her confinement, Mary becomes an expert on the science of color vision and understands all the physical and neurological facts about how humans perceive color. However, she herself has never actually seen any colors firsthand. The experiment raises the question: what happens when Mary finally steps out of her monochromatic environment and sees a vibrant color, such as red, for the first time? According to Jackson, when Mary finally sees the color red, she gains new knowledge, that is- what red truly looks like. This suggests that the subjective experience of seeing red provides a distinct kind of information that cannot be fully captured by objective, physical descriptions alone. The thought experiment is designed to demonstrate that there is an aspect of consciousness, often referred to as "qualia," that goes beyond physical explanations, challenging purely physicalist accounts of the mind. However, some argue that the philosophical zombie actually cannot prove physicalism is wrong. Here are some counter-arguments against philosophical zombie argument : Inconceivability: Critics like Daniel Dennett argue that if a being acts indistinguishably from a conscious being, it must, by necessity, be conscious. Thus, p-zombies are not genuinely conceivable—they are a contradiction in terms. Dennett, a prominent philosopher and cognitive scientist, suggests that if a being behaves indistinguishably from a conscious being, it must be conscious itself because the behavior is a manifestation of the processes we associate with consciousness. This reasoning challenges the concept of p-zombies, which as we mentioned were introduced by philosopher David Chalmers as hypothetical beings who act exactly like conscious beings but lack inner experiences. They would hypothetically react to stimuli, hold conversations, and express emotions like conscious humans, but without any subjective experience. Dennett argues that p-zombies are not genuinely conceivable because if a being behaves exactly like a conscious person, they must also possess consciousness. According to Dennett, the concept of a p-zombie implies that consciousness is a distinct, non-physical property. He rejects this, arguing that consciousness is not separate from the physical processes occurring in the brain. This view is rooted in functionalism and the idea that mental states can be fully explained by the physical and functional processes of the brain. For example, imagine a robot programmed to act exactly like a human: it could hold conversations, detect and respond to emotions, and even write poetry. Dennett would argue that if such a robot perfectly replicated the behaviors and responses of a conscious being, it would essentially possess consciousness by virtue of its functioning, even if it did not have a brain made of organic matter. Circular Reasoning: This criticism points out that p-zombie arguments assume a conclusion within their premises: they begin by assuming that consciousness is non-physical and use that assumption to argue against physicalism. This fallacy becomes evident in the following way: proponents of p-zombies often start by presuming that consciousness has non-physical properties and use that assumption to argue against physicalist views of consciousness. To understand this critique, consider the standard p-zombie thought experiment presented by David Chalmers. He proposes that we can conceive of beings who look and behave like us in every way but lack subjective experience, or qualia. If such beings are conceivable, Chalmers argues, this suggests that consciousness cannot be reduced to physical processes alone, and thus physicalism (the view that everything about the mind can be explained by physical processes) is false. However, critics point out that Chalmers's argument relies on an assumption about the non-physical nature of consciousness to even define a p-zombie. By defining a p-zombie as physically identical to a conscious being but lacking consciousness, he presupposes that consciousness is something over and above physical processes—a non-physical phenomenon. He then uses this presupposition to conclude that consciousness cannot be fully explained by physicalism, which is the circular reasoning critics highlight. For example, a critic might argue that the mere conceptualization of a p-zombie does not prove that such entities are metaphysically possible. Instead, the concept of a p-zombie relies on our intuitions about consciousness being something different from brain processes, which physicalists might reject as incorrect. A physicalist would instead argue that a being that behaves like us must necessarily have the same mental states, as mental states are defined by their physical correlates. Thus, opponents of the p-zombie thought experiment, like Dennett, contend that it doesn't provide a genuine challenge to physicalism because it begs the question. They believe the argument against physicalism is embedded within the assumptions used to define p-zombies, making it circular and unpersuasive. Functionalism: This viewpoint suggests that mental states are constituted solely by their functional role—by their causal relations to sensory inputs, behavioral outputs, and other mental states. Thus, any being that functionally behaves like a human must have conscious experiences identical to a human's. Essentially, this viewpoint posits that what makes something a mental state is its causal relations to sensory inputs, behavioral outputs, and other mental states. Therefore, any entity capable of fulfilling these roles should possess the same mental experiences, regardless of the specific material composition of its brain or body. A classic example illustrating this concept involves pain. According to functionalism, what matters about the experience of pain is not that it's caused by a particular type of neural activity (e.g., C-fiber stimulation in humans), but rather that it serves specific functions like producing avoidance behavior, triggering emotional responses, and motivating decisions to protect the body. Thus, if an alien species or an artificial intelligence system could functionally replicate this pattern of responses and interactions, functionalism asserts that they, too, would be experiencing pain, even if their neural architecture is vastly different. This framework challenges the idea of p-zombies because it insists that any being that behaves indistinguishably from a conscious human would necessarily have the same conscious experiences. According to functionalism, consciousness isn't a mystical property separate from physical processes but is a result of the functional roles these processes fulfill. Critics of the p-zombie argument, like Daniel Dennett, leverage functionalism to argue that p-zombies are conceptually incoherent. If a hypothetical being behaves and reacts to the world in the same way a conscious person does, then, by the functionalist account, it is necessarily conscious. Dennett's famous "intentional stance" further supports this by suggesting that if treating something as a conscious agent reliably predicts its behavior, then it should be considered a conscious agent. Moreover, functionalism provides a theoretical basis for understanding artificial intelligence and the consciousness of non-human entities. For instance, if a computer program could replicate all the functional aspects of human cognition, many functionalists would argue that the program could be considered conscious. Functionalism presents a compelling challenge to p-zombie thought experiments by denying that there could be an entity that behaves in every way like a conscious human but lacks consciousness itself. Instead, it emphasizes that mental states are fully defined by the patterns of interactions and behaviors associated with them. Ok, so who is right here? The answer is, currently no one knows, but here are some statistics that I hope you find helpful: A 2013 survey of professional philosophers by Bourget and Chalmers found that 36% said P Zombies were conceivable but metaphysically impossible; 23% said they were metaphysically possible; 16% said they were inconceivable; and 25% responded "other". In 2020, the same survey yielded almost identical results: "inconceivable" 16%, conceivable but impossible 37%, "metaphysically possible" 24%, and "other" 23%. So here you go, If you want to learn more about the topics I shared today, you can check out the further reading list in the description, and if you want to learn more random knowledge, please subscribe. I am Shao from What People Also Ask, see you next time.
B2 中上級 Philosophical Zombies (P-Zombies): Are They the Key to Understanding Consciousness? 50 0 Jay に公開 2024 年 05 月 20 日 シェア シェア 保存 報告 動画の中の単語