字幕表 動画を再生する
When we finished last time,
we were looking at John Stuart Mill's
attempt to reply to the critics of Bentham's utilitarianism.
In his book utilitarianism, Mill tries to show that critics
to the contrary it is possible within the utilitarian framework
to distinguish between higher and lower pleasures.
It is possible to make qualitative distinctions of worth and we tested
that idea with the Simpsons and the Shakespeare excerpts.
And the results of our experiment seem to call into question
Mill's distinction because a great many of you reported that you prefer
the Simpsons but that you still consider Shakespeare to be
the higher or the worthier pleasure.
That's the dilemma with which our experiment confronts Mill.
What about Mill's attempt to account for the especially weighty character
of individual rights and justice in chapter five of utilitarianism.
He wants to say that individual rights are worthy of special respect.
In fact, he goes so far as to say that justice is
the most sacred part and the most incomparably binding part
of morality.
But the same challenge could be put to this part of Mill's defense.
Why is justice the chief part and the most binding part of our morality?
Well, he says because in the long run,
if we do justice and if we respect rights,
society as a whole will be better off in the long run.
Well, what about that?
What if we have a case where making an exception and
violating individual rights actually will make people better off
in the long run?
Is it all right then to use people?
And there is a further objection that could be raised
against Mill's case for justice and rights.
Suppose the utilitarian calculus in the long run
works out as he says it will such that respecting people's rights
is a way of making everybody better off in the long run.
Is that the right reason?
Is that the only reason to respect people?
If the doctor goes in and yanks the organs from
the healthy patient who came in for a checkup
to save five lives,
there would be adverse effects in the long run.
Eventually, people would learn about this and
would stop going in for checkups.
Is it the right reason?
Is the only reason that you as a doctor won't yank the organs
out of the healthy patient that you think, well,
if I use him in this way, in the long run more lives would be lost?
Or is there another reason having to do with intrinsic respect
for the person as an individual?
And if that reason matters and it's not so clear
that even Mill's utilitarianism can take account of it,
fully to examine these two worries or objections,
to Mill's defense we need to push further.
And we need to ask in the case of higher or worthier pleasures
are there theories of the good life that can provide
independent moral standards for the worth of pleasure?
If so, what do they look like? That's one question.
In the case of justice and rights, if we suspect that Mill
is implicitly leaning on notions of human dignity
or respect for person that are not strictly speaking utilitarian,
we need to look to see whether there are some stronger theories
of rights that can explain the intuition which even Mill shares,
the intuition that the reason for respecting individuals
and not using them goes beyond even utility in the long run.
Today, we turn to one of those strong theories of rights.
Strong theories of right say individuals matter not just as
instruments to be used for a larger social purpose
or for the sake of maximizing utility,
individuals are separate beings with separate lives worthy of respect.
And so it's a mistake, according to strong theories
of rights, it's a mistake to think about justice
or law by just adding up preferences and values.
The strong rights theory we turn to today is
libertarianism.
Libertarianism takes individual rights seriously.
It's called libertarianism because it says
the fundamental individual right is the right to liberty
precisely because we are separate individual beings.
We're not available to any use that the society
might desire or devise precisely because we are
individual separate human beings.
We have a fundamental right to liberty,
and that means a right to choose freely,
to live our lives as we please
provided we respect other people's rights to do the same.
That's the fundamental idea.
Robert Nozick, one of the libertarian philosophers
we read for this course, puts it this way:
Individuals have rights.
So strong and far reaching are these rights that they
raise the question of what, if anything, the state may do.
So what does libertarianism say about the role of government
or of the state?
Well, there are three things that most modern states do
that on the libertarian theory of rights are
illegitimate or unjust.
One of them is paternalist legislation.
That's passing laws that protect people from themselves,
seatbelt laws, for example, or motorcycle helmet laws.
The libertarian says it may be a good thing
if people wear seatbelts
but that should be up to them and the state,
the government, has no business coercing them,
us, to wear seatbelts by law.
It's coercion, so no paternalist legislation, number one.
Number two, no morals legislation.
Many laws try to promote the virtue of citizens
or try to give expression to the moral values of the society as a whole.
Libertarian say that's also a violation of the right to liberty.
Take the example of, well, a classic example
of legislation authored in the name of promoting morality
traditionally have been laws that prevent sexual intimacy
between gays and lesbians.
The libertarian says nobody else is harmed,
nobody else's rights are violated,
so the state should get out of the business entirely of
trying to promote virtue or to enact morals legislation.
And the third kind of law or policy that is ruled out
on the libertarian philosophy is any taxation or other policy
that serves the purpose of redistributing income or wealth
from the rich to the poor.
Redistribution is a... if you think about it,
says the libertarian is a kind of coercion.
What it amounts to is theft by the state or by the majority,
if we're talking about a democracy, from people who happen to
do very well and earn a lot of money.
Now, Nozick and other libertarians allow that there can be
a minimal state that taxes people for the sake of what everybody needs,
the national defense, police force,
judicial system to enforce contracts and property rights,
but that's it.
Now, I want to get your reactions to this third feature
of the libertarian view.
I want to see who among you agree with that idea and who disagree and why.
But just to make it concrete and to see what's at stake,
consider the distribution of wealth in the United States.
United States is among the most inegalitarian society as far as
the distribution of wealth of all the advanced democracies.
Now, is this just or unjust?
Well, what does the libertarian say?
Libertarian says you can't know just from the facts I've just given you.
You can't know whether that distribution is just or unjust.
You can't know just by looking at a pattern or a distribution or
result whether it's just or unjust.
You have to know how it came to be.
You can't just look at the end stage or the result.
You have to look at two principles.
The first he calls justice in acquisition or in initial holdings.
And what that means simply is did people get the things they used
to make their money fairly?
So we need to know was there justice in the initial holdings?
Did they steal the land or the factory or the goods
that enabled them to make all that money?
If not, if they were entitled to whatever it was
that enabled them to gather the wealth,
the first principle is matched.
The second principle is did the distribution arise from
the operation of free consent, people buying and trading
on the market?
As you can see, the libertarian idea of justice corresponds to
a free market conception of justice provided people got what they used
fairly, didn't steal it, and provided the distribution results
from the free choice of individual's buying and selling things,
the distribution is just.
And if not, it's unjust.
So let's, in order to fix ideas for this discussion,
take an actual example.
Who's the wealthiest person in the United States...
wealthiest person in the world? Bill Gates.
It is. That's right. Here he is.
You'd be happy, too.
Now, what's his net worth? Anybody have any idea?