字幕表 動画を再生する
-
I have been asked to be the last speaker of today.
-
I know, of course, that you will all be extremely tired at this moment.
-
But the fun thing is that I'll be talking
-
about logic and creativity.
-
And you see the subtitle: "A False Opposition".
-
It will mainly be about logic.
-
But the fun thing is that you don't have to think. OK?
-
So, just let your mind go all possible ways
-
'cause I will try to show you -- what I want to try to show you is this.
-
In western philosophy for over more than 2000 years --
-
I'm not exaggerating here, for more than 2000 years,
-
there was always the idea that
-
you have logicians on one hand,
-
and you have creative people on the other hand.
-
And the two will never meet.
-
So, you have this image of a logician,
-
which does not correspond to me,
-
namely, the kind of person with a very strict mind who follows
-
the conclusions he or she has to follow with an inevitable force,
-
whereas the creative mind can explore all the possibilities, etc.
-
Well, first of all, if you do logical analysis you get problems.
-
And, what I will do, in the time that I have at my disposal,
-
I will show you some of these problems.
-
And they are deep, deep, deep problems,
-
also extremely amusing.
-
And if you want to try to solve problems, you need creativity.
-
So, that's me being logical,
-
logical analysis needs creativity.
-
It's even better.
-
If you want to inverse the whole story,
-
if you want to be creative, you have to explore.
-
But, if you want to explore, then you need maps for exploration.
-
Such maps need logical analysis,
-
so, inevitably, creativity needs logical analysis.
-
So, right. This is the end of the talk.
-
(Laughter)
-
I have made my point, so --
-
(Applause)
-
But I still have 16 minutes. So, OK. Let's have some fun.
-
OK. I'll start with a very simple problem.
-
One of the problems that logicians think about a great deal
-
is how do we define things.
-
It's something that -- we don't do it on a daily basis.
-
Very often if somebody asks you: "What is this?"
-
Then what you do, you give it a description,
-
you try to define what it is.
-
OK, let's take one of the most famous examples
-
from the British philosopher Bertrand Russell,
-
and it goes as follows.
-
Imagine a village, and in the village is a barber,
-
and the barber is that person that shaves people.
-
Now, imagine that you give the following definition.
-
Who is the barber in the village? Well, that's that person
-
who shaves everybody who does not shave himself.
-
Sounds OK. People who don't shave themselves go to to the barber --
-
it's a very neat village, clean people, I'm not living there. (Laughter)
-
They go to the barber to get shaved.
-
And then you realize this definition is no good
-
because the only question you have to ask, "What should the poor barber do?"
-
Imagine the barber getting up in the morning.
-
He goes into the bathroom, looks in the mirror,
-
and he says: "Should I shave myself?
-
Ah, no, I can't, because I'm the person
-
who shaves everybody who does not shave himself.
-
Now, if I would shave myself, then I can't go to my barber, but that's me.
-
So, I can't shave myself."
-
But then, of course, he wonders,
-
"Should then I not shave myself?"
-
He says: "Well, that's no good, because then
-
I belong to those people who come to me to get shaved.
-
So, now, I have to shave myself."
-
So, he has to shave himself,
-
if and only if he does not have to shave himself.
-
Right. Can you get out of this?
-
Sure. There's a very easy solution.
-
Take a woman.
-
(Laughter)
-
(Applause)
-
And, since I always have clever students
-
in my college classes, one of them said,
-
"Yes, but did you take into account the woman with a beard in the circus?"
-
Okay, so that's why it's added a woman without a beard. Yeah.
-
You can of course say, "Reject the definition."
-
OK, fine, but what are you then going to do?
-
So the question you then ask --
-
and this is a question that is still an open question,
-
we have no good, decent answer to it.
-
Namely, how can we decide, when I give you a definition,
-
how can you decide that that definition is OK?
-
Well, the answer is, you can't.
-
Here's another example, one of my great favorites.
-
OK. Watch this.
-
Since time is staring at me at this very moment
-
this is a perfect example.
-
Suppose you have the following definition.
-
If you have two watches, "one" and "two",
-
then "one" is a better watch than "two"
-
if "one" gives you more often correct time.
-
That seems reasonable. No, it isn't.
-
It's a very bad idea because -- (Laughs) --
-
if you have a broken watch that gives you
-
two times a day the correct time -- Right?
-
Whereas if you have a watch that runs ahead one minute
-
it never gives you the right time.
-
So the broken watch is better than the other one.
-
OK?
-
It's of course a bad definition because it doesn't tell you
-
that you have to know when it gives you the correct time.
-
Bad definition. OK. Let's forget about definitions.
-
Let's take something more fun.
-
Truth. Ah! (Laughs)
-
I was very pleased that TED has as a subtitle,
-
"Ideas Worth Spreading".
-
Not "True Ideas Worth Spreading"
-
because otherwise I would have not been here today.
-
Because I will show you that I have no idea what truth is.
-
Why? OK. Follow me for a moment.
-
Assume the following.
-
If I say something that is meaningful
-
then it is either true or false.
-
At least in first order we can accept it,
-
I know we have plenty of occasions where we have doubts.
-
Is it raining, or not raining? It's drizzling. OK.
-
But in that case, is it drizzling, or not drizzling?
-
OK, fine.
-
Keep the world simple for a moment.
-
Either true or false. Right?
-
Either the one or the other.
-
That seams, OK -- that's trivial.
-
And this one too. Not both of them.
-
You can't say of something that is both true and false.
-
That's excluded. Right?
-
Doesn't it sound perfectly reasonable?
-
It doesn't. (Laughs)
-
And this is the reason why.
-
The famous liar paradox. OK.
-
This sentence says, "This sentence is not true."
-
So this sentence says of itself that it is not true.
-
It is meaningful. I assume that everybody here present
-
knows what this statement says.
-
It says about itself that is not true.
-
So, we understand it. So that means
-
it must have a truth value: either true or false.
-
But now what happens?
-
If it is true, then it turns out that is not true.
-
Of course. Assume that a sentence is true.
-
Then what the sentence says must be the case.
-
What does it say?
-
That it is not true.
-
So if it is true, it is not true.
-
That's OK. That's fine. That's OK.
-
You can conclude from that that is not true.
-
So then assume that is not true.
-
What then?
-
Well, if it is not true,
-
then that is exactly what the sentence says.
-
Now, if something says exactly what is the case, then it is true.
-
So, if it's not true, false, then it is true.
-
It is true, if and only if it is false.
-
So, there you have it.
-
Ah! Then you say: "How can we get out of this?"
-
First a warning. I have to confess I'm a professor,
-
so I'm a teacher and I can't resist teaching.
-
So, here's a short moment of teaching.
-
You will learn something
-
you can embarrass logicians with. OK?
-
So I'm now working against my own Trade Union,
-
the United Force of Logicians Worldwide.
-
If you now meet the logicians you can say,
-
"Tell me, how about that problem," -- namely this problem.
-
The paradox that I've just shown you is also known
-
as the Epimenides paradox.
-
And it goes as follows.
-
All Cretans -- you are on the island of Creta,
-
and a Cretan says to you,
-
"I have to warn you, all Cretans are liars."
-
Now, what are you supposed to do here?
-
Well, very funny, first of all a bit of theology.
-
If you say logic, you say theology.
-
What would theologians be without logicians
-
to prove the existence of God -- which, of course, doesn't work.
-
Neither does the opposite, but that's another problem.
-
And that's a different talk, by the way, also.
-
Which I have, so, OK, worth spreading.
-
I told you, I'm doing the thinking for you. OK?
-
So you don't have to think.
-
Actually, the Epimenides paradox,
-
the first reference you get is in the bible.
-
It's in the Epistle of Paul to Titus.
-
Titus, being sent off with his family, yes, his family,
-
to Crete, to convert people there.
-
And Paul gives him a warning.
-
And that's chapter 1, 1-12, -- you may remain seated --
-
"One of themselves, a prophet of their own said,
-
'Cretans are always liars, evil beasts, idle gluttons.' "
-
And then Paul makes a horrible mistake.
-
He says, "This testimony is true." (Laughs)
-
Which proves that in the early Roman-Catholic church
-
there weren't that many logicians around.
-
Because they would have said,
-
"Paul, don't write this, I mean, it's silly."
-
Because what you have it's the following situation.
-
There is no paradox.
-
So any logician will tell you,
-
"Oh, this is definitely a paradox."
-
It isn't. Why?
-
Because it is not so that all Cretans are liars.
-
Because you know it has been said by a Cretan,
-
so if what he says it would be the case,
-
then they are all liars, so he must be a liar.
-
OK. Now what is the meaning of "It is not so that all Cretans are liars"?
-
That is, that some of them are liars
-
and some of them speak the truth.
-
Now if it so happens that the Cretan that is telling you this,
-
is a liar, everything is fine.
-
It's basically a liar who has told you a lie.
-
If he had been a truth teller,
-
then you would have had a problem.
-
And that's exactly what Paul wrote.
-
I'm not going into a theological discussion here,
-
Hence this must be -- OK, what?
-
How to solve it?
-
I'll be very brief. We don't know.
-
One of the brute -- yes, well, I mean --
-
(Applause)
-
This is no exaggeration.
-
There are plenty of logicians who would say,
-
"Don't say such thing."
-
"I'm now saying a lie." "Shut up."
-
Or you could say, well, there's more than true and false.
-
You have true, you have false, and you have stuff in between.
-
That's a possibility. It's not a good possibility.
-
Or, why not -- and this is something that logicians
-
have been working on since the 1950's-60's --
-
why can't we reason with sentences,
-
statements that are both true and false?
-
If you say, "What's typical for a sentence like,
-
'It's Saturday today?' "
-
Well, in this case it is true.
-
Tomorrow it will be false. Fine.
-
What is typical for a sentence such as,
-
"I'm rambling." Well, you have to decide.
-
And if you then ask,
-
what's typical for "This sentence is not true."
-
Answer, that is is both true and false.
-
That's the characteristic of it. Ah, lovely.
-
OK. Let's get closer to the world.
-
I'm sure you are all familiar with Zeno's paradoxes.
-
And we have a solution, that's nice.