字幕表 動画を再生する
-
Well, I’m speaking today with Dr. Stephen Hicks, who is a professor of philosophy in
-
the Department of Philosophy at Rockford University in Illinois. Professor Hicks has written a
-
book—he’s written several books—but he’s written one in particular that I wanted
-
to talk to him about today called Explaining Postmodernism: Skepticism and Socialism from
-
Rousseau to Foucault, which was published a fair while ago now, in 2004, but I think
-
has become even more pertinent and relevant today.
-
I have talked a lot to my viewers about your book, and so let’s talk about Postmodernism
-
and its relationship with Neo-Marxism. So maybe you could tell the viewers here a little
-
more about yourself and how you got interested in this.
-
Well, I finished graduate school in philosophy in the early 90s, originally from Canada,
-
born in Toronto. At that point Pittsburgh and Indiana had the two strongest philosophy
-
of science and logic programs, and that’s what I was interested in at the time. And
-
so upon a professor’s recommendation, I ended up at Indiana, and it worked out very
-
nicely for me.
-
So most of my graduate work was actually in epistemology, philosophy of science, logic,
-
some cognitive science issues as well. So a lot of the epistemological and philosophical/linguistic
-
issues that come up in Postmodernism—the groundwork so to speak was laid for that.
-
When I finished grad school and started teaching full-time, came to Rockford University. I
-
was teaching in an honors program, and the way that program worked was—it was essentially
-
a Great Books program—and so it was like getting a second education, wonderfully. But
-
the way it was done was that each course was taught by two professors to our honor students.
-
So the professors would be from different departments, so I was paired with literature
-
professors, history professors, and so on. And this was now the middle of the 90s.
-
I started to hear about thinkers I had not read. I’d kind-of heard about them, but
-
now I was reading them more closely and finding that in history and literature and sociology
-
and anthropology, names like Derrida and Foucault and the others, if not omnipresent, were huge
-
names. So I realized I had a gap in my education to fill. So I started reading deeply in them.
-
My education in some ways was broad in the history of philosophy but narrow at the graduate
-
school level and I had focused mostly on Anglo-American philosophy, so my understanding of the Continental
-
traditions was quite limited. But by the time I got to the end of the 90s, I realized there
-
was something significant going on coming out of Continental philosophy. And that’s
-
where the book [published 2004] came out of. When you say significant, what do you mean
-
by that? Do you mean intellectually? Do you mean socially? Politically? There’s lots
-
of different variants of “significant.”When you say significant, what do you mean by that?
-
Do you mean intellectually? Do you mean socially? Politically? There’s lots of different variants
-
of “significant.” At that point, “intellectually.” This
-
was still in the 1990s so postmodernism was not yet (outside of, say, art) a cultural
-
force, but it was strongly an intellectual force in that. At that point, young Ph.D.s
-
coming out of sociology, literary criticism, some sub-disciplines in the law (if you’re
-
getting Ph.D. in the law), historiography and so on, and certainly in departments in
-
philosophy still dominated by Continental traditional philosophy: almost all of them
-
are primarily being schooled in what we now call postmodern thinkers, so the leading gurus
-
are people like Derrida, Lyotard, from whom we get the label post-modern condition, Foucault
-
and the others. So maybe you could walk us through what you
-
learned, because people are unfamiliar ... I mean, you were advanced in your education,
-
including in philosophy, and still recognized your ignorance, say, with regards to postmodern
-
thinking, so that’s obviously a condition that is shared by a large number of people.
-
Postmodernism is one of those words like Existentialism that covers an awful lot of territory, and
-
so maybe we could zero in on exactly what that means, and who these thinkers were: Derrida,
-
Foucault, and Lyotard, and what you learned about them.
-
Fair enough. Well, all of the thinkers you just named—they think broadly, they think
-
strategically, and they do have a very strong historical perspective on their disciplines,
-
and at the same time they are trying to assess where they think we are culturally, politically,
-
socially—and all of them are making a very dramatic claim: that to some extent or in
-
some way Modernism has either ended or it has reached its nadir, or all of the … kind
-
of the pathologies and negative traits within the modern world are reaching a culmination
-
in their generation, and so it’s time for us to both recognize that Modernism has come
-
to an end, and that we need some sort of new intellectual framework, a post-modern-like
-
framework. And the Modernism that they’re criticizing,
-
how would you characterize that? That’s Enlightenment values? Scientific rationalism?
-
How would you characterize it, exactly? All of those would be elements of it. But
-
then of course there are some discipline-specific differences: so literature people and philosophy
-
people and historians will use Modernism slightly differently. But the idea at core is that
-
if you look at the pre-modern world—essentially the world of the Middle Ages, say—that that
-
was itself broken up by a series of revolutions: the Renaissance, Reformation, Counter Reformation,
-
early scientific revolutions—and all of this is going on in historically short chunks
-
of time: 1500s and 1600s.
-
And so if you look at both the intellectual world and the social world, comparing, say,
-
the 1400s with the 1700s, culturally and intellectually you’re in a different universe at that point.
-
So the features then of the modern world—now I’m going to use my philosophical labels
-
here—are that we are now naturalistic in our thinking. We are no longer primarily supernaturalistic
-
in our thinking. So we might still be open to the idea that there’s a God or some sort
-
of supernatural dimension, the way Deists are, but first and foremost we’re taking
-
the natural world as a more or less self-contained, self-governing world that operates according
-
to cause and effect, and we’re going to study it in its terms.
-
We’re not seeing the natural world as derivative of a “higher” world or that everything
-
that happens in the natural world is part of “God’s plan” where we read omens
-
and so forth into everything.
-
So metaphysically then there’s been a revolution: We’re naturalistic.
-
Epistemologically—in terms of knowledge—there also has been a revolution. How do we know
-
the important truths? How do we acquire the beliefs that we’re fundamentally going to
-
commit our lives to? Well, by the time we become Moderns we take experience seriously,
-
personal experience. We do that more rigorously and we’re developing scientific method (the
-
way of organizing the data), we’re taking logic and all the sophisticated tools of rationality
-
and developing those increasingly ...
-
And so our opposition then is: Either you know something because you can experience
-
it and verify it for yourself, or we've done the really hard work of scientific method
-
and as a result of what comes out of that, that’s what we can call knowledge or our
-
best approximation to that.
-
And that’s also revolutionary because the prior intellectual framework was much more
-
intellectually authoritarian in its framework. You would accept in the Catholic tradition
-
the authority of the Church. And who are you to question the authority of the Church? And
-
who are you to mouth empirical-rational arguments against the authority of the Church?
-
Or, you take the authority of Scripture, or you accept on faith that you've had a mystical
-
revelation of some sort.
-
So, in all of those cases you have non-rational epistemologies that are dominating intellectual
-
discourse. That is all by and large swept away in the modern world.
-
Okay, so prior to the emergence of the modern world, we’ll say, people are dominated essentially
-
by their willingness to adhere to a shared tradition and that shared tradition is somewhat
-
tyrannically enforced. But there’s no real alternative in terms of epistemology [epistemology:
-
the theory of knowledge, especially with regard to its methods, validity and scope: the investigation
-
of what distinguishes justified belief from opinion] let’s say. And then as the modern
-
world emerges, people discover the technologies of science and the value of rigorously applied
-
method and the comparison of shared experiences and that makes us technologically powerful
-
in a new way and philosophically different from what we were before. ]
-
Yes, the shared tradition phrase that you added there, that’s an important one. So
-
I’d say in the early modern world there’s not necessarily a skepticism about shared
-
traditions—so there would be an acceptance of shared traditions—but the idea is that
-
you would not uncritically accept your tradition. You may accept your tradition, but only after
-
you've thought it through and made your own independent judgment.
-
Okay, okay, so you’re elevated to the status of someone who’s capable of taking a stance
-
with regards to the tradition, and assessing its presuppositions and so forth.
-
Absolutely. So there’s an elevation of the individual
-
and the critical intellect along with the elaboration of the scientific method. Okay,
-
so then we might note, perhaps, that that’s a tremendously effective transformation, although
-
maybe it leads in a somewhat nihilistic direction metaphysically—we can leave that to the
-
side. But it’s a very, very successful revolution, because by the time, at least the beginning
-
of the 20th century comes along, there’s this staggering (and of course before that,
-
the Industrial Revolution), there’s this staggering transformation of technology and
-
technological and conceptual power, and then a stunning increase in the standard of living.
-
And that starts at about 1890, to really move exponentially in the 1890s, or at least to
-
get to the really steep part of the exponential curve. Okay, so that seems to be going well.
-
So what is it that the postmodernists are objecting to precisely?
-
Just on those two issues: (1) the metaphysical naturalism, and then (2) the elevation of
-
kind of a critical empiricism and a belief that we can, through science—even not necessarily
-
a science, but social scientists and so on—we can come to understand powerful general principles
-
about humanity and social systems.
-
Those two revolutions both are then subjected to counter-attacks.
-
And again, what happens in this case is there is a revolution. Probably by the time we get
-
to 1800—the height of the Enlightenment—there are the beginnings of more powerful skeptical
-
traditions that come to be developed, so thinkers are starting to say things like: Well, if
-
scientific method at root is based on the evidence of the senses—we observe the natural
-
world: that’s our first point of contact—and then on the basis of that we form abstractions,
-
and then we put those abstractions into propositions, and then we take those propositions and put
-
them in networks that we call theories, and so on—so we start to critically examine
-
each of the elements of scientific method, and over time, weaknesses in the existing
-
accounts of how all of those “rational operations” work come to be teased out, and philosophy
-
then starts to go down a more skeptical path.
-
So if, for example, you take perception as fundamental—it’s you know, the individual
-
subject’s first point of contact with the natural world—then you have to immediately
-
deal with issues of perceptual illusions, or the possibility that people will have hallucinations,
-
or that the way you report your perceptual experience is at odds with how I report my
-
perceptual experience.
-
Tell me if I’ve got this right. So, with the dawning of the “Empirical Age,” let’s
-
say, there’s this idea that you can derive valid information from sense data—especially
-
if you contrast that sense data rigorously with that of others—okay? So that’s sort
-
of the foundation for the scientific method in some sense.
-
But then—I think this is with Immanuel Kant—there’s an objection to that, which is that, Well,
-
you can’t make the presupposition that that sense data enters your cognitive apparatus,
-
your apparatus of understanding, without a priori structuring, and it seems to me that
-
that’s where the postmodernists really go after the modernists. It’s that, given that
-
you have to have a very complex perceptual structure (that modern people might say was
-
instantiated as a consequence of biological evolution), you can’t make the case that
-
what you’re receiving from the external world is something like “pure information”:
-
it’s always subject—to some very-difficult-to-delimit degree—to “interpretation.”
-
And then you also have to take into account the fact of that a priori structure and what
-
it might mean for your concept of “objective reality.” And that’s Kant, I think, if
-
I’ve got that right.
-
Right. Well, the postmodernists will use both of those strategies: (1) the anti-empiricist
-
strategy, and (2) the anti-rationalist strategy. And what’s important about Kant is that
-
Kant is integrating both of those “anti” strategies. So in the generations before Kant,
-
the skeptical arguments about perception which were directed against the empiricists … the
-
empiricists want to say that everything is based on observational data, but then if you
-
don’t have good answers about hallucinations and relativity and illusions and so forth,
-
then it seems like your intellectual structure, whatever it seems to be, if it’s based on
-
probabilistic or possibly faulty perceptual data—then the whole thing is a tottering
-
mess. [Empiricism: the theory stating that knowledge comes only or primarily from sensory
-
experience. Empirical research, including experiments and validated measurement tools,
-
guide the scientific method.]
-
And by the time we get to Kant, the Empiricist tradition is largely unable to respond to
-
those kinds of objections. And so Kant is recognizing and saying: All right, we’ve
-
been trying now for a couple of centuries, we haven’t been able to do so successfully—we’re
-
not going to be able to do so.
-
Now, you also nicely emphasized that one of the other responses had been on the Rationalist
-
side, which is to say, “Well, no you don’t start with pure empirical data—instead we
-
do have perhaps some innate a priori structures built into the human mind—how they got there,
-
maybe they’re put there by God, maybe they’re put there naturalistically or whatever—but
-
what enables us to have legitimate knowledge is that our empirical data comes in and it
-
is filtered and structured by these pre-existing cognitive structures as well.”
-
Now the problem with that side of the line—and this is also well worked out by the time you
-
get to the Kantians—is to say: Well, if you’re starting with in-built cognitive
-
structures, and everything that comes in, so to speak, goes through this structuring
-
machine and you’re aware of the outputs—because that’s what is presented to your mind—well
-
how do you know those in-built structures have anything to do with the way reality actually
-
is out there?
-
It seems like then what you are stuck with is the end result of a subjective processing,
-
and there is no way for you, so to speak, to “jump outside of your head” to compare
-
the end result with the way the world actually is, independently of how your mind has structured
-
the awareness.
-
So once again, you’re stuck in a rather subjective place.
-
And again, the importance of Kant here is then he’s also looking at this more Rationalist
-
tradition and he’s saying, Well look, again we’ve been trying now for a couple of centuries
-
to work these things out from Descartes to Spinoza, Leibniz and the others, and Rationalism
-
also has reached a dead end, so we’re not going to be able to do so.
-
So Kant is, in effect, standing at the end of these two traditions and saying, “You
-
know, the skeptics have it right on both sides: both the Empiricist and the Rationalist traditions
-
fail. There is no way for us to objectively come to know an external reality. We’re
-
stuck in some sort of deep subjectivism.”
-
Okay, so I don’t know now whether to talk a little bit about the American Pragmatic
-
approach to that, or whether to ... Maybe we should go ahead and continue our discussion
-
of the postmodernists, because they’re developing these claims.
-
Absolutely, and some of the postmodernists do describe themselves as Neo-Pragmatists,
-
like Richard Rorty for example. So yes, that’s exactly a direction that’s worth going.
-
Okay, okay. So my understanding of that, if I was going to defend the Modernist tradition,
-
let’s say, I would say that we have instantiated within us an a priori perceptual structure
-
that’s a consequence of millions—billions of years for that matter—of biological evolution,
-
and it has emerged in tandem with continual correction of its presuppositions by the selection
-
process. But it’s still subject to error because we have a very limited viewpoint as
-
specific individuals, and not only are we limited, but we can also make, you might say,
-
moral errors, and I’ll get back to that, that cloud our judgment.
-
And so, in an attempt to “expand our purview” and rectify those errors, we do two things:
-
(1) We test our hypothesis practically against the world, which is to say, we say, “Here’s
-
a theory of reality.” We act it out. If the theory of reality is sufficiently correct,
-
when we act it out, we get what we want, and then that’s sufficient proof for the validity
-
of the theory. It’s not absolute proof, but it’s sufficient proof. And then the
-
other thing we do (and I think this has been paid attention to much less except by thinkers